CHESTERTON-St Thomas Aquinas - THE PERMANENT PHILOSOPHY


VIII

THE SEQUEL TO ST. THOMAS



It is often said that St. Thomas. unlike St. Francis,

did not permit in his work the indescribable element of poetry.

As, for instance, that there is little reference to any

pleasure in the actual flowers and fruit of natural things,

though any amount of concern with the buried roots of nature.

And yet I confess that, in reading his philosophy, I have

a very peculiar and powerful impression analogous to poetry.

Curiously enough, it is in some ways more analogous to painting,

and reminds me very much of the effect produced by the best

of the modern painters, when they throw a strange and almost crude

light upon stark and rectangular objects, or seem to be groping

for rather than grasping the very pillars of the subconscious mind.

It is probably because there is in his work a quality which

is Primitive, in the best sense of a badly misused word;

but any how, the pleasure is definitely not only of the reason,

but also of the imagination.

Perhaps the impression is connected with the fact that painters deal

with things without words. An artist draws quite gravely the grand

curves of a pig; because he is not thinking of the word pig.

There is no thinker who is so unmistakably thinking about things

and not being misled by the indirect influence of words,

as St. Thomas Aquinas. It is true in that sense that he has not

the advantage of words, any more than the disadvantage of words.

Here he differs sharply, for instance, from St. Augustine who was,

among other things a wit. He was also a sort of prose poet,

with a power over words in their atmospheric and emotional aspect;

so that his books abound with beautiful passages that rise

in the memory like strains of music; the illi in vos saeviant;

or the unforgettable cry, "Late I have loved thee,

O Ancient Beauty!" It is true that there is little or nothing

of this kind in St. Thomas; but if he was without the higher uses

of the mere magic of words, he was also free from that abuse of it,

by mere sentimentalists or self-centred artists, which can become

merely morbid and a very black magic indeed. And truly it is by

some such comparison with the purely introspective intellectual.

that we may find a hint about the real nature of the thing

I describe, or rather fail to describe; I mean the elemental

and primitive poetry that shines through all his thoughts;

and especially through the thought with which all his thinking begins.

It is the intense rightness of his sense of the relation between

the mind and the real thing outside the mind.

That strangeness of things, which is the light in all poetry,

and indeed in all art, is really connected with their otherness;

or what is called their objectivity. What is subjective must

be stale; it is exactly what is objective that is in this

imaginative manner strange. In this the great contemplative

is the complete contrary of that false contemplative,

the mystic who looks only into his own soul, the selfish artist

who shrinks from the world and lives only in his own mind.

According to St. Thomas, the mind acts freely of itself,

but its freedom exactly consists in finding a way out to liberty

and the light of day; to reality and the land of the living.

In the subjectivist, the pressure of the world forces

the imagination inwards. In the Thomist, the energy of the mind

forces the imagination outwards, but because the images

it seeks are real things. All their romance and glamour,

so to speak, lies in the fact that they are real things;

things not to be found by staring inwards at the mind.

The flower is a vision because it is not only a vision.

Or, if you will, it is a vision because it is not a dream.

This is for the poet the strangeness of stones and trees

and solid things; they are strange because they are solid.

I am putting it first in the poetical manner, and indeed it needs

much more technical subtlety to put it in the philosophical manner.

According to Aquinas, the object becomes a part of the mind;

nay, according to Aquinas, the mind actually becomes

the object. But, as one commentator acutely puts it,

it only becomes the object and does not create the object.

In other words, the object is an object; it can and does

exist outside the mind, or in the absence of the mind.

And therefore it enlarges the mind of which it becomes a part.

The mind conquers a new province like an emperor; but only

because the mind has answered the bell like a servant.

The mind has opened the doors and windows, because it is

the natural activity of what is inside the house to find out

what is outside the house. If the mind is sufficient to itself,

it is insufficient for itself. For this feeding upon fact

is itself; as an organ it has an object which is objective;

this eating of the strange strong meat of reality.

Note how this view avoids both pitfalls; the alternative abysses

of impotence. The mind is not merely receptive, in the sense

that it absorbs sensations like so much blotting-paper; on that

sort of softness has been based all that cowardly materialism,

which conceives man as wholly servile to his environment.

On the other hand, the mind is not purely creative, in the sense

that it paints pictures on the windows and then mistakes them

for a landscape outside. But the mind is active, and its activity

consists in following, so far as the will chooses to follow,

the light outside that does really shine upon real landscapes.

That is what gives the indefinably virile and even adventurous

quality to this view of life; as compared with that which holds

that material inferences pour in upon an utterly helpless mind,

or that which holds that psychological influences pour

out and create an entirely baseless phantasmagoria.

In other words, the essence of the Thomist common sense is

that two agencies are at work; reality and the recognition

of reality; and their meeting is a sort of marriage.

Indeed it is very truly a marriage, because it is fruitful;

the only philosophy now in the world that really is fruitful.

It produces practical results, precisely because it is

the combination of an adventurous mind and a strange fact.

M. Maritain has used an admirable metaphor, in his book Theonas,

when he says that the external fact fertilises the internal intelligence,

as the bee fertilises the flower. Anyhow, upon that marriage,

or whatever it may be called, the whole system of St. Thomas is founded;

God made Man so that he was capable of coming in contact with reality;

and those whom God hath joined, let no man put asunder.

Now, it is worthy of remark that it is the only working philosophy.

Of nearly all other philosophies it is strictly true that their

followers work in spite of them, or do not work at all.

No sceptics work sceptically; no fatalists work fatalistically;

all without exception work on the principle that it is

possible to assume what it is not possible to believe.

No materialist who thinks his mind was made up for him, by mud

and blood and heredity, has any hesitation in making up his mind.

No sceptic who believes that truth is subjective has any hesitation

about treating it as objective.

Thus St. Thomas work has a constructive quality absent from almost

all cosmic systems after him. For he is already building a house,

while the newer speculators are still at the stage of testing the rungs

of a ladder, demonstrating the hopeless softness of the unbaked bricks.

chemically analysing the spirit in the spirit-level, and generally

quarrelling about whether they can even make the tools that will

make the house. Aquinas is whole intellectual aeons ahead of them,

over and above the common chronological sense of saving a man

is in advance of his age; he is ages in advance of our age.

For he has thrown out a bridge across the abyss of the first doubt,

and found reality beyond and begun to build on it.

Most modern philosophies are not philosophy but philosophic doubt;

that is, doubt about whether there can be any philosophy.

If we accept St. Thomas's fundamental act or argument in the acceptance

of reality, the further deductions from it will be equally real;

they will be things and not words. Unlike Kant and most of

the Hegelians, he has a faith that is not merely a doubt about doubt.

It is not merely what is commonly called a faith about faith;

it is a faith about fact. From this point he can go forward,

and deduce and develop and decide, like a man planning a city

and sitting in a judgment-seat. But never since that time has

any thinking man of that eminence thought that there is any real

evidence for anything, not even the evidence of his senses,

that was strong enough to bear the weight of a definite deduction.

From all this we may easily infer that this philosopher does not

merely touch on social things, or even take them in his stride

to spiritual things; though that is always his direction.

He takes hold of them, he has not only a grasp of them,

but a grip. As all his controversies prove, he was perhaps

a perfect example of the iron hand in the velvet glove.

He was a man who always turned his full attention to anything;

and he seems to fix even passing things as they pass.

To him even what was momentary was momentous. The reader

feels that any small point of economic habit or human accident

is for the moment almost scorched under the converging rays

of a magnifying lens. It is impossible to put in these pages

a thousandth part of the decisions on details of life that may be

found in his work; it would be like reprinting the law-reports

of an incredible century of just judges and sensible magistrates.

We can only touch on one or two obvious topics of this kind.

I have noted the need to use modern atmospheric words for certain

ancient atmospheric things; as in saying that St. Thomas was what

most modern men vaguely mean by an Optimist. In the same way,

he was very much what they vaguely mean by a Liberal. I do not

mean that any of his thousand political suggestions would suit any

such definite political creed; if there are nowadays any definite

political creeds. I mean, in the same sense, that he has a sort

of atmosphere of believing in breadth and balance and debate.

He may not be a Liberal by the extreme demands of the moderns for we

seem always to mean by the moderns the men of the last century,

rather than this. He was very much of a Liberal compared

with the most modern of all modern; for they are nearly all

of them turning into Fascists and Hitlerites. But the point

is that he obviously preferred the sort of decisions that

are reached by deliberation rather than despotic action;

and while, like all his contemporaries and coreligionists,

he has no doubt that true authority may be authoritative,

he is rather averse to the whole savour of its being arbitrary.

He is much less of an Imperialist than Dante, and even his

Papalism is not very Imperial. He is very fond of phrases

like "a mob of free men" as the essential material of a city;

and he is emphatic upon the fact that law, when it ceases

to be justice, ceases even to be law.

If this work were controversial, whole chapters could be given

to the economics as well as the ethics of the Thomist system.

It would be easy to show that, in this matter, he was a prophet as well

as a philosopher. He foresaw from the first the peril of that mere

reliance on trade and exchange, which was beginning about his time;

and which has culminated in a universal commercial collapse in our time.

He did not merely assert that Usury is unnatural, though in saying

that he only followed Aristotle and obvious common sense, which was

never contradicted by anybody until the time of the commercialists,

who have involved us in the collapse. The modern world began

by Bentham writing the Defence of Usury, and it has ended after

a hundred years in even the vulgar newspaper opinion finding

Finance indefensible. But St. Thomas struck much deeper than that.

He even mentioned the truth, ignored during the long idolatry of trade,

that things which men produce only to sell are likely to be worse

in quality than the things they produce in order to consume.

Something of our difficulty about the fine shades of Latin will be felt

when we come to his statement that there is always a certain inhonestas

about trade. For inhonestas does not exactly mean dishonesty.

It means approximately "something unworthy," or, more nearly perhaps,

"something not quite handsome." And he was right; for trade,

in the modern sense, does mean selling something for a little more

than it is worth, nor would the nineteenth century economists have

denied it. They would only have said that he was not practical;

and this seemed sound while their view led to practical prosperity.

Things are a little different now that it has led to universal bankruptcy.

Here, however, we collide with a colossal paradox of history.

The Thomist philosophy and theology, quite fairly compared

with other philosophies like the Buddhist or the Monist,

with other theologies like the Calvinist or the Christian Scientist,

is quite obviously a working and even a fighting system;

full of common sense and constructive confidence; and therefore

normally full of hope and promise. Nor is this hope vain

or this promise unfulfilled. In this not very hopeful

modern moment, there are no men so hopeful as those who are

today looking to St. Thomas as a leader in a hundred crying

questions of craftsmanship and ownership and economic ethics.

There is undoubtedly a hopeful and creative Thomism in our time.

But we are none the less puzzled by the fact that this did

not immediately follow on St. Thomas's time. It is true that

there was a great march of progress in the thirteenth century;

and in some things, such as the status of the peasant, matters had

greatly improved by the end of the Middle Ages. But nobody can

honestly say that Scholasticism had greatly improved by the end

of the Middle Ages. Nobody can tell how far the popular spirit

of the Friars had helped the later popular medieval movements;

or how far this great Friar, with his luminous rules of justice

and his lifelong sympathy with the poor, may have indirectly

contributed to the improvement that certainly occurred.

But those who followed his method, as distinct from his

moral spirit, degenerated with a strange rapidity; and it was

certainly not in the Scholastics that the improvement occurred.

Of some of the Scholastics we can only say that they took every

thing that was worst in Scholasticism and made it worse.

They continued to count the steps of logic; but every step of logic

took them further from common sense. They forgot how St. Thomas

had started almost as an agnostic; and seemed resolved to leave

nothing in heaven or hell about which anybody could be agnostic.

They were a sort of rabid rationalists, who would have left

no mysteries in the Faith at all. In the earliest Scholasticism

there is something that strikes a modern as fanciful and pedantic;

but, properly understood, it has a fine spirit in its fancy.

It is the spirit of freedom; and especially the spirit of free will.

Nothing seems more quaint, for instance, than the speculations

about what would have happened to every vegetable or animal

or angel, if Eve had chosen not to eat the fruit of the tree.

But this was originally full of the thrill of choice;

and the feeling that she might have chosen otherwise.

It was this detailed detective method that was followed,

without the thrill of the original detective story.

The world was cumbered with countless tomes, proving by logic

a thousand things that can be known only to God. They developed

all that was really sterile in Scholasticism, and left for us

all that is really fruitful in Thomism.

There are many historical explanations. There is the Black Death,

which broke the back of the Middle Ages; the consequent

decline in clerical culture, which did so much to provoke

the Reformation. But I suspect that there was another cause also;

which can only be stated by saving that the contemporary fanatics,

who controverted with Aquinas, left their own school behind them;

and in a sense that school triumphed after all. The really

narrow Augustinians, the men who saw the Christian life only as

the narrow way, the men who could not even comprehend the great

Dominican's exultation in the blaze of Being, or the glory of God

in all his creatures, the men who continued to insist feverishly

on every text, or even on every truth, that appeared pessimistic

or paralysing, these gloomy Christians could not be extirpated

from Christendom; and they remained and waited for their chance.

The narrow Augustinians, the men who would have no science or reason

or rational use of secular things, might have been defeated

in controversy, but they had an accumulated passion of conviction.

There was an Augustinian monastery in the North where it was

near to explosion.

Thomas Aquinas had struck his blow; but he had not entirely settled

the Manichees. The Manichees are not so easily settled; in the sense of

settled forever. He had insured that the main outline of the Christianity

that has come down to us should be supernatural but not anti-natural;

and should never be darkened with a false spirituality to the oblivion

of the Creator and the Christ who was made Man. But as his tradition

trailed away into less liberal or less creative habits of thought,

and as his medieval society fell away and decayed through

other causes, the thing against which he had made war crept back

into Christendom. A certain spirit or element in the Christian religion,

necessary and sometimes noble but always needing to be balanced

by more gentle and generous elements in the Faith, began once more

to strengthen, as the framework of Scholasticism stiffened or split.

The Fear of the Lord, that is the beginning of wisdom, and therefore

belongs to the beginnings, and is felt in the first cold hours before

the dawn of civilisation; the power that comes out of the wilderness

and rides on the whirlwind and breaks the gods of stone; the power

before which the eastern nations are prostrate like a pavement;

the power before which the primitive prophets run naked and shouting,

at once proclaiming and escaping from their god; the fear that is

rightly rooted in the beginnings of every religion true or false:

the fear of the Lord, that is the beginning of wisdom; but not the end.

It is often remarked as showing the ironical indifference of rulers

to revolutions, and especially the frivolity of those who are

called the Pagan Popes of the Renaissance, in their attitude

to the Reformation, that when the Pope first heard of the first

movements of Protestantism, which had started in Germany,

he only said in an offhand manner that it was "some quarrel

of monks". Every Pope of course was accustomed to quarrels among

the monastic orders; but it has always been noted as a strange

and almost uncanny negligence that he could see no more than

this in the beginnings of the great sixteenth century schism.

And yet, in a somewhat more recondite sense, there is

something to be said for what he has been blamed for saving.

In one sense, the schismatics had a sort of spiritual ancestry

even in mediaeval times.

It will be found earlier in this book; and it was a quarrel of monks.

We have seen how the great name of Augustine, a name never mentioned

by Aquinas without respect but often mentioned without agreement

covered an Augustinian school of thought naturally lingering

longest in the Augustinian Order. The difference, like every

difference between Catholics, was only a difference of emphasis.

The Augustinians stressed the idea of the impotence of man

before God, the omniscience of God about the destiny of man,

the need for holy fear and the humiliation of intellectual pride,

more than the opposite and corresponding truths of free will or

human dignity or good works. In this they did in a sense continue

the distinctive note of St. Augustine, who is even now regarded

as relatively the determinist doctor of the Church. But there

is emphasis and emphasis; and a time was coming when emphasising

the one side was to mean flatly contradicting the other.

Perhaps, after all, it did begin with a quarrel of monks;

but the Pope was yet to learn how quarrelsome a monk could be.

For there was one particular monk in that Augustinian monastery

in the German forests, who may be said to have had a single

and special talent for emphasis; for emphasis and nothing

except emphasis; for emphasis with the quality of earthquake.

He was the son of a slatecutter; a man with a great voice and a

certain volume of personality; brooding, sincere, decidedly morbid;

and his name was Martin Luther. Neither Augustine nor the Augustinians

would have desired to see the day of that vindication of the

Augustinian tradition; but in one sense, perhaps, the Augustinian

tradition was avenged after all.

It came out of its cell again, in the day of storm and ruin,

and cried out with a new and mighty voice for an elemental and

emotional religion, and for the destruction of all philosophies.

It had a peculiar horror and loathing of the great Greek philosophies,

and of the scholasticism that had been founded on those philosophies.

It had one theory that was the destruction of all theories;

in fact it had its own theology which was itself the death

of theology. Man could say nothing to God, nothing from God,

nothing about God, except an almost inarticulate cry for mercy

and for the supernatural help of Christ, in a world where all natural

things were useless. Reason was useless. Will was useless.

Man could not move himself an inch any more than a stone.

Man could not trust what was in his head any more than a turnip.

Nothing remained in earth or heaven, but the name of Christ lifted

in that lonely imprecation; awful as the cry of a beast in pain.

We must be just to those huge human figures, who are in fact

the hinges of history. However strong, and rightly strong,

be our own controversial conviction, it must never mislead us

into thinking that something trivial has transformed the world.

So it is with that great Augustinian monk, who avenged all

the ascetic Augustinians of the Middle Ages; and whose broad

and burly figure has been big enough to block out for four

centuries the distant human mountain of Aquinas. It is not,

as the moderns delight to say, a question of theology.

The Protestant theology of Martin Luther was a thing that

no modern Protestant would be seen dead in a field with;

or if the phrase be too flippant, would be specially anxious

to touch with a barge-pole. That Protestantism was pessimism;

it was nothing but bare insistence on the hopelessness

of all human virtue, as an attempt to escape hell.

That Lutheranism is now quite unreal; more modern phases of

Lutheranism are rather more unreal; but Luther was not unreal.

He was one of those great elemental barbarians, to whom it

is indeed given to change the world. To compare those two

figures hulking so big in history, in any philosophical sense,

would of course be futile and even unfair. On a great map like

the mind of Aquinas, the mind of Luther would be almost invisible.

But it is not altogether untrue to say, as so many journalists

have said without caring whether it was true or untrue,

that Luther opened an epoch; and began the modern world.

He was the first man who ever consciously used his consciousness

or what was later called his Personality. He had as a fact a rather

strong personality. Aquinas had an even stronger personality;

he had a massive and magnetic presence; he had an intellect that could

act like a huge system of artillery spread over the whole world;

he had that instantaneous presence of mind in debate, which alone

really deserves the name of wit. But it never occurred to him to use

anything except his wits, in defence of a truth distinct from himself.

It never occurred to Aquinas to use Aquinas as a weapon.

There is not a trace of his ever using his personal advantages,

of birth or body or brain or breeding, in debate with anybody.

In short, he belonged to an age of intellectual unconsciousness,

to an age of intellectual innocence, which was very intellectual.

Now Luther did begin the modern mood of depending on things not

merely intellectual. It is not a question of praise or blame;

it matters little whether we say that he was a strong personality,

or that he was a bit of a big bully. When he quoted a Scripture text,

inserting a word that is not in Scripture, he was content to shout back

at all hecklers: "Tell them that Dr. Martin Luther will have it so!"

That is what we now call Personality. A little later it was

called Psychology. After that it was called Advertisement

or Salesmanship. But we are not arguing about advantages

or disadvantages. It is due to this great Augustinian pessimist to say,

not only that he did triumph at last over the Angel of the Schools,

but that he did in a very real sense make the modern world.

He destroyed Reason; and substituted Suggestion.

It is said that the great Reformer publicly burned the Summa Theologica

and the works of Aquinas; and with the bonfire of such books this book

may well come to an end. They say it is very difficult to burn a book;

and it must have been exceedingly difficult to burn such a mountain

of books as the Dominican had contributed to the controversies

of Christendom. Anyhow, there is something lurid and apocalyptic about

the idea of such destruction, when we consider the compact complexity of

all that encyclopaedic survey of social and moral and theoretical things.

All the close-packed definitions that excluded so many errors

and extremes; all the broad and balanced judgments upon the clash

of loyalties or the choice of evils; all the liberal speculations

upon the limits of government or the proper conditions of justice;

all the distinctions between the use and abuse of private property;

all the rules and exceptions about the great evil of war; all the

allowances for human weakness and all the provisions for human health;

all this mass of medieval humanism shrivelled and curled up in smoke

before the eves of its enemy; and that great passionate peasant

rejoiced darkly, because the day of the Intellect was over.

Sentence by sentence it burned, and syllogism by syllogism;

and the golden maxims turned to golden flames in that last and dying glory

of all that had once been the great wisdom of the Greeks. The great

central Synthesis of history, that was to have linked the ancient

with the modern world, went up in smoke and, for half the world,

was forgotten like a vapour.

For a time it seemed that the destruction was final.

It is still expressed in the amazing fact that (in the North)

modern men can still write histories of philosophy, in which

philosophy stops with the last little sophists of Greece and Rome;

and is never heard of again until the appearance of such a

third-rate philosopher as Francis Bacon. And yet this small book,

which will probably do nothing else, or have very little other value,

will be at least a testimony to the fact that the tide has turned

once more. It is four hundred years after; and this book, I hope

(and I am happy to say I believe) will probably be lost and

forgotten in the flood of better books about St. Thomas Aquinas,

which are at this moment pouring from every printing-press in Europe,

and even in England and America. Compared with such books it

is obviously a very slight and amateurish production; but it is

not likely to be burned, and if it were, it would not leave even

a noticeable gap in the pouring mass of new and magnificent work,

which is now daily dedicated to the philosophia perennis;

to the Everlasting Philosophy.





End of this Project Gutenberg of Australia eBook

St. Thomas Aquinas by G. K. Chesterton





-----------------------------------------------------------------

More information about this eBook is provided at the top of this file.

Our US site is at http://gutenberg.net or http://promo.net/pg

It takes us, at a rather conservative estimate, fifty hours to get any

eBook selected, entered, proofread, edited, copyright searched and

analyzed.

The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation in the United States has

been created to secure a secure future for Project Gutenberg

All donations should be made to:

Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation


PMB 113

1739 University Ave.

Oxford, MS 38655-4109 USA

***

** The Legal Small Print **

Why is this "Small Print!" statement here? You know: lawyers. They tell

us you might sue us if there is something wrong with your copy of this

eBook, even if you got it for free from someone other than us, and even

if what's wrong is not our fault. So, among other things, this

"Small Print!" statement disclaims most of our liability to you. It also

tells you how you may distribute copies of this eBook if you want to.

*BEFORE!* YOU USE OR READ THIS eBook

By using or reading any part of this PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBook, you

indicate that you understand, agree to and accept this "Small Print!"

statement. If you do not, you can receive a refund of the money (if any)

you paid for this eBook by sending a request within 30 days of receiving

it to the person you got it from. If you received this eBook on a

physical medium (such as a disk), you must return it with your request.

ABOUT PROJECT GUTENBERG-TM eBookS

This PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBook is in the "public domain" in Australia

Among other things, this means that, in Australia, no one owns a copyright

on or for this work, so the Project (and you!) can copy and distribute it

in Australia without permission and without paying copyright royalties.

Special rules, set forth below, apply if you wish to copy and distribute

this eBook under the "PROJECT GUTENBERG" trademark.

Please do not use the "PROJECT GUTENBERG" trademark to market any

commercial products without permission.

To create these eBooks, the Project expends considerable efforts to

identify, transcribe and proofread public domain works. Despite these

efforts, the Project's eBooks and any medium they may be on may contain

"Defects". Among other things, Defects may take the form of incomplete,

inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other

intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other

eBook medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be

read by your equipment.


LIMITED WARRANTY; DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES

But for the "Right of Replacement or Refund" described below, [1] Michael

Hart and the Foundation (and any other party you may receive this eBook

from as a PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBook) disclaims all liability to you for

damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees, and [2] YOU HAVE NO


REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE OR UNDER STRICT LIABILITY, OR FOR BREACH OF

WARRANTY OR CONTRACT, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO INDIRECT,

CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES, EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF


CHESTERTON-St Thomas Aquinas - THE PERMANENT PHILOSOPHY