CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - THE FALLACY OF SUCCESS


ON RUNNING AFTER ONE'S HAT



I feel an almost savage envy on hearing that London has been flooded in

my absence, while I am in the mere country. My own Battersea has been, I

understand, particularly favoured as a meeting of the waters. Battersea

was already, as I need hardly say, the most beautiful of human

localities. Now that it has the additional splendour of great sheets of

water, there must be something quite incomparable in the landscape (or

waterscape) of my own romantic town. Battersea must be a vision of

Venice. The boat that brought the meat from the butcher's must have shot

along those lanes of rippling silver with the strange smoothness of the

gondola. The greengrocer who brought cabbages to the corner of the

Latchmere Road must have leant upon the oar with the unearthly grace of

the gondolier. There is nothing so perfectly poetical as an island; and

when a district is flooded it becomes an archipelago.

Some consider such romantic views of flood or fire slightly lacking in

reality. But really this romantic view of such inconveniences is quite

as practical as the other. The true optimist who sees in such things an

opportunity for enjoyment is quite as logical and much more sensible

than the ordinary "Indignant Ratepayer" who sees in them an opportunity

for grumbling. Real pain, as in the case of being burnt at Smithfield or

having a toothache, is a positive thing; it can be supported, but

scarcely enjoyed. But, after all, our toothaches are the exception, and

as for being burnt at Smithfield, it only happens to us at the very

longest intervals. And most of the inconveniences that make men swear or

women cry are really sentimental or imaginative inconveniences--things

altogether of the mind. For instance, we often hear grown-up people

complaining of having to hang about a railway station and wait for a

train. Did you ever hear a small boy complain of having to hang about a

railway station and wait for a train? No; for to him to be inside a

railway station is to be inside a cavern of wonder and a palace of

poetical pleasures. Because to him the red light and the green light on

the signal are like a new sun and a new moon. Because to him when the

wooden arm of the signal falls down suddenly, it is as if a great king

had thrown down his staff as a signal and started a shrieking tournament

of trains. I myself am of little boys' habit in this matter. They also

serve who only stand and wait for the two fifteen. Their meditations may

be full of rich and fruitful things. Many of the most purple hours of my

life have been passed at Clapham Junction, which is now, I suppose,

under water. I have been there in many moods so fixed and mystical that

the water might well have come up to my waist before I noticed it

particularly. But in the case of all such annoyances, as I have said,

everything depends upon the emotional point of view. You can safely

apply the test to almost every one of the things that are currently

talked of as the typical nuisance of daily life.

For instance, there is a current impression that it is unpleasant to

have to run after one's hat. Why should it be unpleasant to the

well-ordered and pious mind? Not merely because it is running, and

running exhausts one. The same people run much faster in games and

sports. The same people run much more eagerly after an uninteresting;

little leather ball than they will after a nice silk hat. There is an

idea that it is humiliating to run after one's hat; and when people say

it is humiliating they mean that it is comic. It certainly is comic; but

man is a very comic creature, and most of the things he does are

comic--eating, for instance. And the most comic things of all are

exactly the things that are most worth doing--such as making love. A man

running after a hat is not half so ridiculous as a man running after a

wife.

Now a man could, if he felt rightly in the matter, run after his hat

with the manliest ardour and the most sacred joy. He might regard

himself as a jolly huntsman pursuing a wild animal, for certainly no

animal could be wilder. In fact, I am inclined to believe that

hat-hunting on windy days will be the sport of the upper classes in the

future. There will be a meet of ladies and gentlemen on some high ground

on a gusty morning. They will be told that the professional attendants

have started a hat in such-and-such a thicket, or whatever be the

technical term. Notice that this employment will in the fullest degree

combine sport with humanitarianism. The hunters would feel that they

were not inflicting pain. Nay, they would feel that they were inflicting

pleasure, rich, almost riotous pleasure, upon the people who were

looking on. When last I saw an old gentleman running after his hat in

Hyde Park, I told him that a heart so benevolent as his ought to be

filled with peace and thanks at the thought of how much unaffected

pleasure his every gesture and bodily attitude were at that moment

giving to the crowd.

The same principle can be applied to every other typical domestic worry.

A gentleman trying to get a fly out of the milk or a piece of cork out

of his glass of wine often imagines himself to be irritated. Let him

think for a moment of the patience of anglers sitting by dark pools, and

let his soul be immediately irradiated with gratification and repose.

Again, I have known some people of very modern views driven by their

distress to the use of theological terms to which they attached no

doctrinal significance, merely because a drawer was jammed tight and

they could not pull it out. A friend of mine was particularly afflicted

in this way. Every day his drawer was jammed, and every day in

consequence it was something else that rhymes to it. But I pointed out

to him that this sense of wrong was really subjective and relative; it

rested entirely upon the assumption that the drawer could, should, and

would come out easily. "But if," I said, "you picture to yourself that

you are pulling against some powerful and oppressive enemy, the struggle

will become merely exciting and not exasperating. Imagine that you are

tugging up a lifeboat out of the sea. Imagine that you are roping up a

fellow-creature out of an Alpine crevass. Imagine even that you are a

boy again and engaged in a tug-of-war between French and English."

Shortly after saying this I left him; but I have no doubt at all that my

words bore the best possible fruit. I have no doubt that every day of

his life he hangs on to the handle of that drawer with a flushed face

and eyes bright with battle, uttering encouraging shouts to himself, and

seeming to hear all round him the roar of an applauding ring.

So I do not think that it is altogether fanciful or incredible to

suppose that even the floods in London may be accepted and enjoyed

poetically. Nothing beyond inconvenience seems really to have been

caused by them; and inconvenience, as I have said, is only one aspect,

and that the most unimaginative and accidental aspect of a really

romantic situation. An adventure is only an inconvenience rightly

considered. An inconvenience is only an adventure wrongly considered.

The water that girdled the houses and shops of London must, if anything,

have only increased their previous witchery and wonder. For as the Roman

Catholic priest in the story said: "Wine is good with everything except

water," and on a similar principle, water is good with everything except

wine.








THE VOTE AND THE HOUSE



Most of us will be canvassed soon, I suppose; some of us may even

canvass. Upon which side, of course, nothing will induce me to state,

beyond saying that by a remarkable coincidence it will in every case be

the only side in which a high-minded, public-spirited, and patriotic

citizen can take even a momentary interest. But the general question of

canvassing itself, being a non-party question, is one which we may be

permitted to approach. The rules for canvassers are fairly familiar to

any one who has ever canvassed. They are printed on the little card

which you carry about with you and lose. There is a statement, I think,

that you must not offer a voter food or drink. However hospitable you

may feel towards him in his own house, you must not carry his lunch

about with you. You must not produce a veal cutlet from your tail-coat

pocket. You must not conceal poached eggs about your person. You must

not, like a kind of conjurer, produce baked potatoes from your hat. In

short, the canvasser must not feed the voter in any way. Whether the

voter is allowed to feed the canvasser, whether the voter may give the

canvasser veal cutlets and baked potatoes, is a point of law on which I

have never been able to inform myself. When I found myself canvassing a

gentleman, I have sometimes felt tempted to ask him if there was any

rule against his giving me food and drink; but the matter seemed a

delicate one to approach. His attitude to me also sometimes suggested a

doubt as to whether he would, even if he could. But there are voters who

might find it worth while to discover if there is any law against

bribing a canvasser. They might bribe him to go away.

The second veto for canvassers which was printed on the little card said

that you must not persuade any one to personate a voter. I have no idea

what it means. To dress up as an average voter seems a little vague.

There is no well-recognised uniform, as far as I know, with civic

waistcoat and patriotic whiskers. The enterprise resolves itself into

one somewhat similar to the enterprise of a rich friend of mine who went

to a fancy-dress ball dressed up as a gentleman. Perhaps it means that

there is a practice of personating some individual voter. The canvasser

creeps to the house of his fellow-conspirator carrying a make-up in a

bag. He produces from it a pair of white moustaches and a single

eyeglass, which are sufficient to give the most common-place person a

startling resemblance to the Colonel at No. 80. Or he hurriedly affixes

to his friend that large nose and that bald head which are all that is

essential to an illusion of the presence of Professor Budger. I do not

undertake to unravel these knots. I can only say that when I was a

canvasser I was told by the little card, with every circumstance of

seriousness and authority, that I was not to persuade anybody to

personate a voter: and I can lay my hand upon my heart and affirm that I

never did.

The third injunction on the card was one which seemed to me, if

interpreted exactly and according to its words, to undermine the very

foundations of our politics. It told me that I must not "threaten a

voter with any consequence whatever." No doubt this was intended to

apply to threats of a personal and illegitimate character; as, for

instance, if a wealthy candidate were to threaten to raise all the

rents, or to put up a statue of himself. But as verbally and

grammatically expressed, it certainly would cover those general threats

of disaster to the whole community which are the main matter of

political discussion. When a canvasser says that if the opposition

candidate gets in the country will be ruined, he is threatening the

voters with certain consequences. When the Free Trader says that if

Tariffs are adopted the people in Brompton or Bayswater will crawl about

eating grass, he is threatening them with consequences. When the Tariff

Reformer says that if Free Trade exists for another year St. Paul's

Cathedral will be a ruin and Ludgate Hill as deserted as Stonehenge, he

is also threatening. And what is the good of being a Tariff Reformer if

you can't say that? What is the use of being a politician or a

Parliamentary candidate at all if one cannot tell the people that if the

other man gets in, England will be instantly invaded and enslaved, blood

be pouring down the Strand, and all the English ladies carried off into

harems. But these things are, after all, consequences, so to speak.

The majority of refined persons in our day may generally be heard

abusing the practice of canvassing. In the same way the majority of

refined persons (commonly the same refined persons) may be heard

abusing the practice of interviewing celebrities. It seems a very

singular thing to me that this refined world reserves all its

indignation for the comparatively open and innocent element in both

walks of life. There is really a vast amount of corruption and hypocrisy

in our election politics; about the most honest thing in the whole mess

is the canvassing. A man has not got a right to "nurse" a constituency

with aggressive charities, to buy it with great presents of parks and

libraries, to open vague vistas of future benevolence; all this, which

goes on unrebuked, is bribery and nothing else. But a man has got the

right to go to another free man and ask him with civility whether he

will vote for him. The information can be asked, granted, or refused

without any loss of dignity on either side, which is more than can be

said of a park. It is the same with the place of interviewing in

journalism. In a trade where there are labyrinths of insincerity,

interviewing is about the most simple and the most sincere thing there

is. The canvasser, when he wants to know a man's opinions, goes and asks

him. It may be a bore; but it is about as plain and straight a thing as

he could do. So the interviewer, when he wants to know a man's opinions,

goes and asks him. Again, it may be a bore; but again, it is about as

plain and straight as anything could be. But all the other real and

systematic cynicisms of our journalism pass without being vituperated

and even without being known--the financial motives of policy, the

misleading posters, the suppression of just letters of complaint. A

statement about a man may be infamously untrue, but it is read calmly.

But a statement by a man to an interviewer is felt as indefensibly

vulgar. That the paper should misrepresent him is nothing; that he

should represent himself is bad taste. The whole error in both cases

lies in the fact that the refined persons are attacking politics and

journalism on the ground of vulgarity. Of course, politics and

journalism are, as it happens, very vulgar. But their vulgarity is not

the worst thing about them. Things are so bad with both that by this

time their vulgarity is the best thing about them. Their vulgarity is at

least a noisy thing; and their great danger is that silence that always

comes before decay. The conversational persuasion at elections is

perfectly human and rational; it is the silent persuasions that are

utterly damnable.

If it is true that the Commons' House will not hold all the Commons, it

is a very good example of what we call the anomalies of the English

Constitution. It is also, I think, a very good example of how highly

undesirable those anomalies really are. Most Englishmen say that these

anomalies do not matter; they are not ashamed of being illogical; they

are proud of being illogical. Lord Macaulay (a very typical Englishman,

romantic, prejudiced, poetical), Lord Macaulay said that he would not

lift his hand to get rid of an anomaly that was not also a grievance.

Many other sturdy romantic Englishmen say the same. They boast of our

anomalies; they boast of our illogicality; they say it shows what a

practical people we are. They are utterly wrong. Lord Macaulay was in

this matter, as in a few others, utterly wrong. Anomalies do matter

very much, and do a great deal of harm; abstract illogicalities do

matter a great deal, and do a great deal of harm. And this for a reason

that any one at all acquainted with human nature can see for himself.

All injustice begins in the mind. And anomalies accustom the mind to the

idea of unreason and untruth. Suppose I had by some prehistoric law the

power of forcing every man in Battersea to nod his head three times

before he got out of bed. The practical politicians might say that this

power was a harmless anomaly; that it was not a grievance. It could do

my subjects no harm; it could do me no good. The people of Battersea,

they would say, might safely submit to it. But the people of Battersea

could not safely submit to it, for all that. If I had nodded their heads

for them for fifty years I could cut off their heads for them at the end

of it with immeasurably greater ease. For there would have permanently

sunk into every man's mind the notion that it was a natural thing for me

to have a fantastic and irrational power. They would have grown

accustomed to insanity.

For, in order that men should resist injustice, something more is

necessary than that they should think injustice unpleasant. They must

think injustice absurd; above all, they must think it startling. They

must retain the violence of a virgin astonishment. That is the

explanation of the singular fact which must have struck many people in

the relations of philosophy and reform. It is the fact (I mean) that

optimists are more practical reformers than pessimists. Superficially,

one would imagine that the railer would be the reformer; that the man

who thought that everything was wrong would be the man to put everything

right. In historical practice the thing is quite the other way;

curiously enough, it is the man who likes things as they are who really

makes them better. The optimist Dickens has achieved more reforms than

the pessimist Gissing. A man like Rousseau has far too rosy a theory of

human nature; but he produces a revolution. A man like David Hume thinks

that almost all things are depressing; but he is a Conservative, and

wishes to keep them as they are. A man like Godwin believes existence to

be kindly; but he is a rebel. A man like Carlyle believes existence to

be cruel; but he is a Tory. Everywhere the man who alters things begins

by liking things. And the real explanation of this success of the

optimistic reformer, of this failure of the pessimistic reformer, is,

after all, an explanation of sufficient simplicity. It is because the

optimist can look at wrong not only with indignation, but with a

startled indignation. When the pessimist looks at any infamy, it is to

him, after all, only a repetition of the infamy of existence. The Court

of Chancery is indefensible--like mankind. The Inquisition is

abominable--like the universe. But the optimist sees injustice as

something discordant and unexpected, and it stings him into action. The

pessimist can be enraged at wrong; but only the optimist can be

surprised at it.

And it is the same with the relations of an anomaly to the logical

mind. The pessimist resents evil (like Lord Macaulay) solely because it

is a grievance. The optimist resents it also, because it is an anomaly;

a contradiction to his conception of the course of things. And it is not

at all unimportant, but on the contrary most important, that this course

of things in politics and elsewhere should be lucid, explicable and

defensible. When people have got used to unreason they can no longer be

startled at injustice. When people have grown familiar with an anomaly,

they are prepared to that extent for a grievance; they may think the

grievance grievous, but they can no longer think it strange. Take, if

only as an excellent example, the very matter alluded to before; I mean

the seats, or rather the lack of seats, in the House of Commons. Perhaps

it is true that under the best conditions it would never happen that

every member turned up. Perhaps a complete attendance would never

actually be. But who can tell how much influence in keeping members away

may have been exerted by this calm assumption that they would stop away?

How can any man be expected to help to make a full attendance when he

knows that a full attendance is actually forbidden? How can the men who

make up the Chamber do their duty reasonably when the very men who built

the House have not done theirs reasonably? If the trumpet give an

uncertain sound, who shall prepare himself for the battle? And what if

the remarks of the trumpet take this form, "I charge you as you love

your King and country to come to this Council. And I know you won't."








CONCEIT AND CARICATURE



If a man must needs be conceited, it is certainly better that he should

be conceited about some merits or talents that he does not really

possess. For then his vanity remains more or less superficial; it

remains a mere mistake of fact, like that of a man who thinks he

inherits the royal blood or thinks he has an infallible system for Monte

Carlo. Because the merit is an unreal merit, it does not corrupt or

sophisticate his real merits. He is vain about the virtue he has not

got; but he may be humble about the virtues that he has got. His truly

honourable qualities remain in their primordial innocence; he cannot see

them and he cannot spoil them. If a man's mind is erroneously possessed

with the idea that he is a great violinist, that need not prevent his

being a gentleman and an honest man. But if once his mind is possessed

in any strong degree with the knowledge that he is a gentleman, he will

soon cease to be one.

But there is a third kind of satisfaction of which I have noticed one or

two examples lately--another kind of satisfaction which is neither a

pleasure in the virtues that we do possess nor a pleasure in the virtues

we do not possess. It is the pleasure which a man takes in the presence

or absence of certain things in himself without ever adequately asking

himself whether in his case they constitute virtues at all. A man will

plume himself because he is not bad in some particular way, when the

truth is that he is not good enough to be bad in that particular way.

Some priggish little clerk will say, "I have reason to congratulate

myself that I am a civilised person, and not so bloodthirsty as the Mad

Mullah." Somebody ought to say to him, "A really good man would be less

bloodthirsty than the Mullah. But you are less bloodthirsty, not because

you are more of a good man, but because you are a great deal less of a

man. You are not bloodthirsty, not because you would spare your enemy,

but because you would run away from him." Or again, some Puritan with a

sullen type of piety would say, "I have reason to congratulate myself

that I do not worship graven images like the old heathen Greeks." And

again somebody ought to say to him, "The best religion may not worship

graven images, because it may see beyond them. But if you do not worship

graven images, it is only because you are mentally and morally quite

incapable of graving them. True religion, perhaps, is above idolatry.

But you are below idolatry. You are not holy enough yet to worship a

lump of stone."

Mr. F. C. Gould, the brilliant and felicitous caricaturist, recently

delivered a most interesting speech upon the nature and atmosphere of

our modern English caricature. I think there is really very little to

congratulate oneself about in the condition of English caricature. There

are few causes for pride; probably the greatest cause for pride is Mr.

F. C. Gould. But Mr. F. C. Gould, forbidden by modesty to adduce this

excellent ground for optimism, fell back upon saying a thing which is

said by numbers of other people, but has not perhaps been said lately

with the full authority of an eminent cartoonist. He said that he

thought "that they might congratulate themselves that the style of

caricature which found acceptation nowadays was very different from the

lampoon of the old days." Continuing, he said, according to the

newspaper report, "On looking back to the political lampoons of

Rowlandson's and Gilray's time they would find them coarse and brutal.

In some countries abroad still, 'even in America,' the method of

political caricature was of the bludgeon kind. The fact was we had

passed the bludgeon stage. If they were brutal in attacking a man, even

for political reasons, they roused sympathy for the man who was

attacked. What they had to do was to rub in the point they wanted to

emphasise as gently as they could." (Laughter and applause.)

Anybody reading these words, and anybody who heard them, will certainly

feel that there is in them a great deal of truth, as well as a great

deal of geniality. But along with that truth and with that geniality

there is a streak of that erroneous type of optimism which is founded on

the fallacy of which I have spoken above. Before we congratulate

ourselves upon the absence of certain faults from our nation or society,

we ought to ask ourselves why it is that these faults are absent. Are we

without the fault because we have the opposite virtue? Or are we without

the fault because we have the opposite fault? It is a good thing

assuredly, to be innocent of any excess; but let us be sure that we are

not innocent of excess merely by being guilty of defect. Is it really

true that our English political satire is so moderate because it is so

magnanimous, so forgiving, so saintly? Is it penetrated through and

through with a mystical charity, with a psychological tenderness? Do we

spare the feelings of the Cabinet Minister because we pierce through all

his apparent crimes and follies down to the dark virtues of which his

own soul is unaware? Do we temper the wind to the Leader of the

Opposition because in our all-embracing heart we pity and cherish the

struggling spirit of the Leader of the Opposition? Briefly, have we left

off being brutal because we are too grand and generous to be brutal? Is

it really true that we are better than brutality? Is it really true

that we have passed the bludgeon stage?

I fear that there is, to say the least of it, another side to the

matter. Is it not only too probable that the mildness of our political

satire, when compared with the political satire of our fathers, arises

simply from the profound unreality of our current politics? Rowlandson

and Gilray did not fight merely because they were naturally pothouse

pugilists; they fought because they had something to fight about. It is

easy enough to be refined about things that do not matter; but men

kicked and plunged a little in that portentous wrestle in which swung to

and fro, alike dizzy with danger, the independence of England, the

independence of Ireland, the independence of France. If we wish for a

proof of this fact that the lack of refinement did not come from mere

brutality, the proof is easy. The proof is that in that struggle no

personalities were more brutal than the really refined personalities.

None were more violent and intolerant than those who were by nature

polished and sensitive. Nelson, for instance, had the nerves and good

manners of a woman: nobody in his senses, I suppose, would call Nelson

"brutal." But when he was touched upon the national matter, there sprang

out of him a spout of oaths, and he could only tell men to "Kill! kill!

kill the d----d Frenchmen." It would be as easy to take examples on the

other side. Camille Desmoulins was a man of much the same type, not only

elegant and sweet in temper, but almost tremulously tender and

humanitarian. But he was ready, he said, "to embrace Liberty upon a pile

of corpses." In Ireland there were even more instances. Robert Emmet was

only one famous example of a whole family of men at once sensitive and

savage. I think that Mr. F.C. Gould is altogether wrong in talking of

this political ferocity as if it were some sort of survival from ruder

conditions, like a flint axe or a hairy man. Cruelty is, perhaps, the

worst kind of sin. Intellectual cruelty is certainly the worst kind of

cruelty. But there is nothing in the least barbaric or ignorant about

intellectual cruelty. The great Renaissance artists who mixed colours

exquisitely mixed poisons equally exquisitely; the great Renaissance

princes who designed instruments of music also designed instruments of

torture. Barbarity, malignity, the desire to hurt men, are the evil

things generated in atmospheres of intense reality when great nations or

great causes are at war. We may, perhaps, be glad that we have not got

them: but it is somewhat dangerous to be proud that we have not got

them. Perhaps we are hardly great enough to have them. Perhaps some

great virtues have to be generated, as in men like Nelson or Emmet,

before we can have these vices at all, even as temptations. I, for one,

believe that if our caricaturists do not hate their enemies, it is not

because they are too big to hate them, but because their enemies are not

big enough to hate. I do not think we have passed the bludgeon stage. I

believe we have not come to the bludgeon stage. We must be better,

braver, and purer men than we are before we come to the bludgeon stage.

Let us then, by all means, be proud of the virtues that we have not got;

but let us not be too arrogant about the virtues that we cannot help

having. It may be that a man living on a desert island has a right to

congratulate himself upon the fact that he can meditate at his ease. But

he must not congratulate himself on the fact that he is on a desert

island, and at the same time congratulate himself on the self-restraint

he shows in not going to a ball every night. Similarly our England may

have a right to congratulate itself upon the fact that her politics are

very quiet, amicable, and humdrum. But she must not congratulate herself

upon that fact and also congratulate herself upon the self-restraint she

shows in not tearing herself and her citizens into rags. Between two

English Privy Councillors polite language is a mark of civilisation, but

really not a mark of magnanimity.

Allied to this question is the kindred question on which we so often

hear an innocent British boast--the fact that our statesmen are

privately on very friendly relations, although in Parliament they sit on

opposite sides of the House. Here, again, it is as well to have no

illusions. Our statesmen are not monsters of mystical generosity or

insane logic, who are really able to hate a man from three to twelve and

to love him from twelve to three. If our social relations are more

peaceful than those of France or America or the England of a hundred

years ago, it is simply because our politics are more peaceful; not

improbably because our politics are more fictitious. If our statesmen

agree more in private, it is for the very simple reason that they agree

more in public. And the reason they agree so much in both cases is

really that they belong to one social class; and therefore the dining

life is the real life. Tory and Liberal statesmen like each other, but

it is not because they are both expansive; it is because they are both

exclusive.

* * * * *








PATRIOTISM AND SPORT.



I notice that some papers, especially papers that call themselves

patriotic, have fallen into quite a panic over the fact that we have

been twice beaten in the world of sport, that a Frenchman has beaten us

at golf, and that Belgians have beaten us at rowing. I suppose that the

incidents are important to any people who ever believed in the

self-satisfied English legend on this subject. I suppose that there are

men who vaguely believe that we could never be beaten by a Frenchman,

despite the fact that we have often been beaten by Frenchmen, and once

by a Frenchwoman. In the old pictures in Punch you will find a

recurring piece of satire. The English caricaturists always assumed that

a Frenchman could not ride to hounds or enjoy English hunting. It did

not seem to occur to them that all the people who founded English

hunting were Frenchmen. All the Kings and nobles who originally rode to

hounds spoke French. Large numbers of those Englishmen who still ride to

hounds have French names. I suppose that the thing is important to any

one who is ignorant of such evident matters as these. I suppose that if

a man has ever believed that we English have some sacred and separate

right to be athletic, such reverses do appear quite enormous and

shocking. They feel as if, while the proper sun was rising in the east,

some other and unexpected sun had begun to rise in the north-north-west

by north. For the benefit, the moral and intellectual benefit of such

people, it may be worth while to point out that the Anglo-Saxon has in

these cases been defeated precisely by those competitors whom he has

always regarded as being out of the running; by Latins, and by Latins of

the most easy and unstrenuous type; not only by Frenchman, but by

Belgians. All this, I say, is worth telling to any intelligent person

who believes in the haughty theory of Anglo-Saxon superiority. But,

then, no intelligent person does believe in the haughty theory of

Anglo-Saxon superiority. No quite genuine Englishman ever did believe in

it. And the genuine Englishman these defeats will in no respect dismay.

The genuine English patriot will know that the strength of England has

never depended upon any of these things; that the glory of England has

never had anything to do with them, except in the opinion of a large

section of the rich and a loose section of the poor which copies the

idleness of the rich. These people will, of course, think too much of

our failure, just as they thought too much of our success. The typical

Jingoes who have admired their countrymen too much for being conquerors

will, doubtless, despise their countrymen too much for being conquered.

But the Englishman with any feeling for England will know that athletic

failures do not prove that England is weak, any more than athletic

successes proved that England was strong. The truth is that athletics,

like all other things, especially modern, are insanely individualistic.

The Englishmen who win sporting prizes are exceptional among Englishmen,

for the simple reason that they are exceptional even among men. English

athletes represent England just about as much as Mr. Barnum's freaks

represent America. There are so few of such people in the whole world

that it is almost a toss-up whether they are found in this or that

country.

If any one wants a simple proof of this, it is easy to find. When the

great English athletes are not exceptional Englishmen they are generally

not Englishmen at all. Nay, they are often representatives of races of

which the average tone is specially incompatible with athletics. For

instance, the English are supposed to rule the natives of India in

virtue of their superior hardiness, superior activity, superior health

of body and mind. The Hindus are supposed to be our subjects because

they are less fond of action, less fond of openness and the open air. In

a word, less fond of cricket. And, substantially, this is probably true,

that the Indians are less fond of cricket. All the same, if you ask

among Englishmen for the very best cricket-player, you will find that he

is an Indian. Or, to take another case: it is, broadly speaking, true

that the Jews are, as a race, pacific, intellectual, indifferent to war,

like the Indians, or, perhaps, contemptuous of war, like the Chinese:

nevertheless, of the very good prize-fighters, one or two have been

Jews.

This is one of the strongest instances of the particular kind of evil

that arises from our English form of the worship of athletics. It

concentrates too much upon the success of individuals. It began, quite

naturally and rightly, with wanting England to win. The second stage was

that it wanted some Englishmen to win. The third stage was (in the

ecstasy and agony of some special competition) that it wanted one

particular Englishman to win. And the fourth stage was that when he had

won, it discovered that he was not even an Englishman.

This is one of the points, I think, on which something might really be

said for Lord Roberts and his rather vague ideas which vary between

rifle clubs and conscription. Whatever may be the advantages or

disadvantages otherwise of the idea, it is at least an idea of procuring

equality and a sort of average in the athletic capacity of the people;

it might conceivably act as a corrective to our mere tendency to see

ourselves in certain exceptional athletes. As it is, there are millions

of Englishmen who really think that they are a muscular race because

C.B. Fry is an Englishman. And there are many of them who think vaguely

that athletics must belong to England because Ranjitsinhji is an Indian.

But the real historic strength of England, physical and moral, has never

had anything to do with this athletic specialism; it has been rather

hindered by it. Somebody said that the Battle of Waterloo was won on

Eton playing-fields. It was a particularly unfortunate remark, for the

English contribution to the victory of Waterloo depended very much more

than is common in victories upon the steadiness of the rank and file in

an almost desperate situation. The Battle of Waterloo was won by the

stubbornness of the common soldier--that is to say, it was won by the

man who had never been to Eton. It was absurd to say that Waterloo was

won on Eton cricket-fields. But it might have been fairly said that

Waterloo was won on the village green, where clumsy boys played a very

clumsy cricket. In a word, it was the average of the nation that was

strong, and athletic glories do not indicate much about the average of a

nation. Waterloo was not won by good cricket-players. But Waterloo was

won by bad cricket-players, by a mass of men who had some minimum of

athletic instincts and habits.

It is a good sign in a nation when such things are done badly. It shows

that all the people are doing them. And it is a bad sign in a nation

when such things are done very well, for it shows that only a few

experts and eccentrics are doing them, and that the nation is merely

looking on. Suppose that whenever we heard of walking in England it

always meant walking forty-five miles a day without fatigue. We should

be perfectly certain that only a few men were walking at all, and that

all the other British subjects were being wheeled about in Bath-chairs.

But if when we hear of walking it means slow walking, painful walking,

and frequent fatigue, then we know that the mass of the nation still is

walking. We know that England is still literally on its feet.

The difficulty is therefore that the actual raising of the standard of

athletics has probably been bad for national athleticism. Instead of the

tournament being a healthy melee into which any ordinary man would

rush and take his chance, it has become a fenced and guarded

tilting-yard for the collision of particular champions against whom no

ordinary man would pit himself or even be permitted to pit himself. If

Waterloo was won on Eton cricket-fields it was because Eton cricket was

probably much more careless then than it is now. As long as the game was

a game, everybody wanted to join in it. When it becomes an art, every

one wants to look at it. When it was frivolous it may have won Waterloo:

when it was serious and efficient it lost Magersfontein.

In the Waterloo period there was a general rough-and-tumble athleticism

among average Englishmen. It cannot be re-created by cricket, or by

conscription, or by any artificial means. It was a thing of the soul. It

came out of laughter, religion, and the spirit of the place. But it was

like the modern French duel in this--that it might happen to anybody. If

I were a French journalist it might really happen that Monsieur

Clemenceau might challenge me to meet him with pistols. But I do not

think that it is at all likely that Mr. C. B. Fry will ever challenge me

to meet him with cricket-bats.








CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - THE FALLACY OF SUCCESS