CHESTERTON-WHAT'S WRONG - III: THE COMMON VISION


IV: THE INSANE NECESSITY

The common conception among the dregs of Darwinian culture

is that men have slowly worked their way out of inequality

into a state of comparative equality. The truth is, I fancy,

almost exactly the opposite. All men have normally and naturally

begun with the idea of equality; they have only abandoned it late

and reluctantly, and always for some material reason of detail.

They have never naturally felt that one class of men was superior

to another; they have always been driven to assume it through

certain practical limitations of space and time.

For example, there is one element which must always tend

to oligarchy--or rather to despotism; I mean the element of hurry.

If the house has caught fire a man must ring up the fire engines;

a committee cannot ring them up. If a camp is surprised by night

somebody must give the order to fire; there is no time to vote it.

It is solely a question of the physical limitations of time and space;

not at all of any mental limitations in the mass of men commanded.

If all the people in the house were men of destiny it would

still be better that they should not all talk into the telephone

at once; nay, it would be better that the silliest man of all should

speak uninterrupted. If an army actually consisted of nothing

but Hanibals and Napoleons, it would still be better in the case

of a surprise that they should not all give orders together.

Nay, it would be better if the stupidest of them all gave the orders.

Thus, we see that merely military subordination, so far from resting

on the inequality of men, actually rests on the equality of men.

Discipline does not involve the Carlylean notion that somebody

is always right when everybody is wrong, and that we must discover

and crown that somebody. On the contrary, discipline means that

in certain frightfully rapid circumstances, one can trust anybody

so long as he is not everybody. The military spirit does not mean

(as Carlyle fancied) obeying the strongest and wisest man.

On the contrary, the military spirit means, if anything, obeying the

weakest and stupidest man, obeying him merely because he is a man,

and not a thousand men. Submission to a weak man is discipline.

Submission to a strong man is only servility.

Now it can be easily shown that the thing we call aristocracy

in Europe is not in its origin and spirit an aristocracy at all.

It is not a system of spiritual degrees and distinctions like,

for example, the caste system of India, or even like the old Greek

distinction between free men and slaves. It is simply the remains

of a military organization, framed partly to sustain the sinking

Roman Empire, partly to break and avenge the awful onslaught

of Islam. The word Duke simply means Colonel, just as the word

Emperor simply means Commander-in-Chief. The whole story is told

in the single title of Counts of the Holy Roman Empire, which merely

means officers in the European army against the contemporary

Yellow Peril. Now in an army nobody ever dreams of supposing

that difference of rank represents a difference of moral reality.

Nobody ever says about a regiment, "Your Major is very humorous

and energetic; your Colonel, of course, must be even more

humorous and yet more energetic " No one ever says, in reporting

a mess-room conversation, "Lieutenant Jones was very witty,

but was naturally inferior to Captain Smith." The essence of an army

is the idea of official inequality, founded on unofficial equality.

The Colonel is not obeyed because he is the best man, but because he is

the Colonel. Such was probably the spirit of the system of dukes

and counts when it first arose out of the military spirit and military

necessities of Rome. With the decline of those necessities it

has gradually ceased to have meaning as a military organization,

and become honeycombed with unclean plutocracy. Even now it

is not a spiritual aristocracy--it is not so bad as all that.

It is simply an army without an enemy--billeted upon the people.

Man, therefore, has a specialist as well as comrade-like aspect;

and the case of militarism is not the only case of such

specialist submission. The tinker and tailor, as well as the soldier

and sailor, require a certain rigidity of rapidity of action:

at least, if the tinker is not organized that is largely why he does

not tink on any large scale. The tinker and tailor often represent

the two nomadic races in Europe: the Gipsy and the Jew; but the Jew

alone has influence because he alone accepts some sort of discipline.

Man, we say, has two sides, the specialist side where he must

have subordination, and the social side where he must have equality.

There is a truth in the saying that ten tailors go to make a man;

but we must remember also that ten Poets Laureate or ten Astronomers Royal

go to make a man, too. Ten million tradesmen go to make Man himself;

but humanity consists of tradesmen when they are not talking shop.

Now the peculiar peril of our time, which I call for argument's sake

Imperialism or Caesarism, is the complete eclipse of comradeship

and equality by specialism and domination.

There are only two kinds of social structure conceivable--

personal government and impersonal government. If my

anarchic friends will not have rules--they will have rulers.

Preferring personal government, with its tact and flexibility,

is called Royalism. Preferring impersonal government,

with its dogmas and definitions, is called Republicanism.

Objecting broadmindedly both to kings and creeds is called Bosh;

at least, I know no more philosophic word for it. You can

be guided by the shrewdness or presence of mind of one ruler,

or by the equality and ascertained justice of one rule; but you must

have one or the other, or you are not a nation, but a nasty mess.

Now men in their aspect of equality and debate adore the idea

of rules; they develop and complicate them greatly to excess.

A man finds far more regulations and definitions in his club,

where there are rules, than in his home, where there is a ruler.

A deliberate assembly, the House of Commons, for instance,

carries this mummery to the point of a methodical madness.

The whole system is stiff with rigid unreason;

like the Royal Court in Lewis Carroll. You would think

the Speaker would speak; therefore he is mostly silent.

You would think a man would take off his hat to stop and put

it on to go away; therefore he takes off his hat to walk out

and puts in on to stop in. Names are forbidden, and a man

must call his own father "my right honorable friend the member

for West Birmingham." These are, perhaps, fantasies of decay:

but fundamentally they answer a masculine appetite.

Men feel that rules, even if irrational, are universal;

men feel that law is equal, even when it is not equitable.

There is a wild fairness in the thing--as there is in tossing up.

Again, it is gravely unfortunate that when critics do attack

such cases as the Commons it is always on the points

(perhaps the few points) where the Commons are right.

They denounce the House as the Talking-Shop, and complain that it

wastes time in wordy mazes. Now this is just one respect in

which the Commons are actually like the Common People. If they

love leisure and long debate, it is be cause all men love it;

that they really represent England. There the Parliament does

approach to the virile virtues of the pothouse.

The real truth is that adumbrated in the introductory section

when we spoke of the sense of home and property, as now we speak

of the sense of counsel and community. All men do naturally

love the idea of leisure, laughter, loud and equal argument;

but there stands a specter in our hall. We are conscious

of the towering modern challenge that is called specialism

or cut-throat competition--Business. Business will have nothing

to do with leisure; business will have no truck with comradeship;

business will pretend to no patience with all the legal

fictions and fantastic handicaps by which comradeship protects

its egalitarian ideal. The modern millionaire, when engaged

in the agreeable and typical task of sacking his own father,

will certainly not refer to him as the right honorable clerk from

the Laburnum Road, Brixton. Therefore there has arisen in modern

life a literary fashion devoting itself to the romance of business,

to great demigods of greed and to fairyland of finance.

This popular philosophy is utterly despotic and anti-democratic;

this fashion is the flower of that Caesarism against which I am

concerned to protest. The ideal millionaire is strong in the

possession of a brain of steel. The fact that the real millionaire

is rather more often strong in the possession of a head of wood,

does not alter the spirit and trend of the idolatry. The essential

argument is "Specialists must be despots; men must be specialists.

You cannot have equality in a soap factory; so you cannot have

it anywhere. You cannot have comradeship in a wheat corner;

so you cannot hare it at all. We must have commercial civilization;

therefore we must destroy democracy." I know that plutocrats hare

seldom sufficient fancy to soar to such examples as soap or wheat.

They generally confine themselves, with fine freshness of mind,

to a comparison between the state and a ship. One anti-democratic

writer remarked that he would not like to sail in a vessel

in which the cabin-boy had an equal vote with the captain.

It might easily be urged in answer that many a ship (the Victoria,

for instance) was sunk because an admiral gave an order which a

cabin-boy could see was wrong. But this is a debating reply;

the essential fallacy is both deeper and simpler. The elementary fact

is that we were all born in a state; we were not all born on a ship;

like some of our great British bankers. A ship still remains

a specialist experiment, like a diving-bell or a flying ship:

in such peculiar perils the need for promptitude constitutes the need

for autocracy. But we live and die in the vessel of the state;

and if we cannot find freedom camaraderie and the popular element

in the state, we cannot find it at all. And the modern doctrine

of commercial despotism means that we shall not find it at all.

Our specialist trades in their highly civilized state cannot

(it says) be run without the whole brutal business of bossing

and sacking, "too old at forty" and all the rest of the filth.

And they must be run, and therefore we call on Caesar. Nobody but

the Superman could descend to do such dirty work.

Now (to reiterate my title) this is what is wrong. This is the huge

modern heresy of altering the human soul to fit its conditions,

instead of altering human conditions to fit the human soul.

If soap boiling is really inconsistent with brotherhood,

so much the worst for soap-boiling, not for brotherhood.

If civilization really cannot get on with democracy, so much

the worse for civilization, not for democracy. Certainly, it would

be far better to go back to village communes, if they really

are communes. Certainly, it would be better to do without soap

rather than to do without society. Certainly, we would sacrifice

all our wires, wheels, systems, specialties, physical science

and frenzied finance for one half-hour of happiness such

as has often come to us with comrades in a common tavern.

I do not say the sacrifice will be necessary; I only say it

will be easy.




PART THREE: FEMINISM, OR THE MISTAKE ABOUT WOMAN



I THE UNMILITARY SUFFRAGETTE

It will be better to adopt in this chapter the same process

that appeared a piece of mental justice in the last.

My general opinions on the feminine question are such as many

suffragists would warmly approve; and it would be easy to state

them without any open reference to the current controversy.

But just as it seemed more decent to say first that I was not

in favor of Imperialism even in its practical and popular sense,

so it seems more decent to say the same of Female Suffrage,

in its practical and popular sense. In other words,

it is only fair to state, however hurriedly, the superficial

objection to the Suffragettes before we go on to the really

subtle questions behind the Suffrage.

Well, to get this honest but unpleasant business over, the objection

to the Suffragettes is not that they are Militant Suffragettes.

On the contrary, it is that they are not militant enough.

A revolution is a military thing; it has all the military virtues;

one of which is that it comes to an end. Two parties fight

with deadly weapons, but under certain rules of arbitrary honor;

the party that wins becomes the government and proceeds to govern.

The aim of civil war, like the aim of all war, is peace.

Now the Suffragettes cannot raise civil war in this

soldierly and decisive sense; first, because they are women;

and, secondly, because they are very few women. But they can

raise something else; which is altogether another pair of shoes.

They do not create revolution; what they do create is anarchy;

and the difference between these is not a question of violence,

but a question of fruitfulness and finality. Revolution of its

nature produces government; anarchy only produces more anarchy.

Men may have what opinions they please about the beheading

of King Charles or King Louis, but they cannot deny that Bradshaw

and Cromwell ruled, that Carnot and Napoleon governed.

Someone conquered; something occurred. You can only knock off

the King's head once. But you can knock off the King's hat any

number of times. Destruction is finite, obstruction is infinite:

so long as rebellion takes the form of mere disorder

(instead of an attempt to enforce a new order) there is no logical

end to it; it can feed on itself and renew itself forever.

If Napoleon had not wanted to be a Consul, but only wanted to be

a nuisance, he could, possibly, have prevented any government

arising successfully out of the Revolution. But such a proceeding

would not have deserved the dignified name of rebellion.

It is exactly this unmilitant quality in the Suffragettes that makes

their superficial problem. The problem is that their action has none

of the advantages of ultimate violence; it does not afford a test.

War is a dreadful thing; but it does prove two points sharply

and unanswerably--numbers, and an unnatural valor. One does discover

the two urgent matters; how many rebels there are alive, and how many

are ready to be dead. But a tiny minority, even an interested minority,

may maintain mere disorder forever. There is also, of course, in the case

of these women, the further falsity that is introduced by their sex.

It is false to state the matter as a mere brutal question of strength.

If his muscles give a man a vote, then his horse ought to have two votes

and his elephant five votes. The truth is more subtle than that;

it is that bodily outbreak is a man's instinctive weapon, like the hoofs

to the horse or the tusks to the elephant. All riot is a threat

of war; but the woman is brandishing a weapon she can never use.

There are many weapons that she could and does use. If (for example)

all the women nagged for a vote they would get it in a month.

But there again, one must remember, it would be necessary to get all

the women to nag. And that brings us to the end of the political surface

of the matter. The working objection to the Suffragette philosophy

is simply that overmastering millions of women do not agree with it.

I am aware that some maintain that women ought to have votes whether the

majority wants them or not; but this is surely a strange and childish case

of setting up formal democracy to the destruction of actual democracy.

What should the mass of women decide if they do not decide their general

place in the State? These people practically say that females may vote

about everything except about Female Suffrage.

But having again cleared my conscience of my merely political

and possibly unpopular opinion, I will again cast back and try

to treat the matter in a slower and more sympathetic style;

attempt to trace the real roots of woman's position in

the western state, and the causes of our existing traditions

or perhaps prejudices upon the point. And for this purpose

it is again necessary to travel far from the modern topic,

the mere Suffragette of today, and to go back to subjects which,

though much more old, are, I think, considerably more fresh.




II: THE UNIVERSAL STICK

Cast your eye round the room in which you sit, and select some three

or four things that have been with man almost since his beginning;

which at least we hear of early in the centuries and often among

the tribes. Let me suppose that you see a knife on the table,

a stick in the corner, or a fire on the hearth. About each of these

you will notice one speciality; that not one of them is special.

Each of these ancestral things is a universal thing;

made to supply many different needs; and while tottering pedants

nose about to find the cause and origin of some old custom,

the truth is that it had fifty causes or a hundred origins.

The knife is meant to cut wood, to cut cheese, to cut pencils,

to cut throats; for a myriad ingenious or innocent human objects.

The stick is meant partly to hold a man up, partly to knock a man down;

partly to point with like a finger-post, partly to balance with

like a balancing pole, partly to trifle with like a cigarette,

partly to kill with like a club of a giant; it is a crutch and a cudgel;

an elongated finger and an extra leg. The case is the same, of course,

with the fire; about which the strangest modern views have arisen.

A queer fancy seems to be current that a fire exists to warm people.

It exists to warm people, to light their darkness, to raise

their spirits, to toast their muffins, to air their rooms,

to cook their chestnuts, to tell stories to their children, to make

checkered shadows on their walls, to boil their hurried kettles,

and to be the red heart of a man's house and that hearth for which,

as the great heathens said, a man should die.

Now it is the great mark of our modernity that people are always

proposing substitutes for these old things; and these substitutes

always answer one purpose where the old thing answered ten. The modern

man will wave a cigarette instead of a stick; he will cut his pencil

with a little screwing pencil-sharpener instead of a knife; and he will

even boldly offer to be warmed by hot water pipes instead of a fire.

I have my doubts about pencil-sharpeners even for sharpening pencils;

and about hot water pipes even for heat. But when we think of all

those other requirements that these institutions answered, there opens

before us the whole horrible harlequinade of our civilization.

We see as in a vision a world where a man tries to cut his throat with

a pencil-sharpener; where a man must learn single-stick with a cigarette;

where a man must try to toast muffins at electric lamps, and see red

and golden castles in the surface of hot water pipes.

The principle of which I speak can be seen everywhere in a

comparison between the ancient and universal things and the modern

and specialist things. The object of a theodolite is to lie level;

the object of a stick is to swing loose at any angle; to whirl

like the very wheel of liberty. The object of a lancet is to lance;

when used for slashing, gashing, ripping, lopping off heads and limbs,

it is a disappointing instrument. The object of an electric light is

merely to light (a despicable modesty); and the object of an asbestos

stove . . . I wonder what is the object of an asbestos stove?

If a man found a coil of rope in a desert he could at least

think of all the things that can be done with a coil of rope;

and some of them might even be practical. He could tow a boat

or lasso a horse. He could play cat's-cradle, or pick oakum.

He could construct a rope-ladder for an eloping heiress, or cord

her boxes for a travelling maiden aunt. He could learn to tie a bow,

or he could hang himself. Far otherwise with the unfortunate

traveller who should find a telephone in the desert. You can

telephone with a telephone; you cannot do anything else with it.

And though this is one of the wildest joys of life, it falls by one

degree from its full delirium when there is nobody to answer you.

The contention is, in brief, that you must pull up a hundred roots,

and not one, before you uproot any of these hoary and simple expedients.

It is only with great difficulty that a modem scientific sociologist

can be got to see that any old method has a leg to stand on.

But almost every old method has four or five legs to stand on.

Almost all the old institutions are quadrupeds; and some of

them are centipedes.

Consider these cases, old and new, and you will observe

the operation of a general tendency. Everywhere there was

one big thing that served six purposes; everywhere now there

are six small things; or, rather (and there is the trouble),

there are just five and a half. Nevertheless, we will not

say that this separation and specialism is entirely useless

or inexcusable. I have often thanked God for the telephone;

I may any day thank God for the lancet; and there is none

of these brilliant and narrow inventions (except, of course,

the asbestos stove) which might not be at some moment

necessary and lovely. But I do not think the most austere

upholder of specialism will deny that there is in these old,

many-sided institutions an element of unity and universality

which may well be preserved in its due proportion and place.

Spiritually, at least, it will be admitted that some all-round

balance is needed to equalize the extravagance of experts.

It would not be difficult to carry the parable of the knife

and stick into higher regions. Religion, the immortal maiden,

has been a maid-of-all-work as well as a servant of mankind.

She provided men at once with the theoretic laws of an unalterable

cosmos and also with the practical rules of the rapid and

thrilling game of morality. She taught logic to the student

and told fairy tales to the children; it was her business

to confront the nameless gods whose fears are on all flesh,

and also to see the streets were spotted with silver and scarlet,

that there was a day for wearing ribbons or an hour for

ringing bells. The large uses of religion have been broken

up into lesser specialities, just as the uses of the hearth

have been broken up into hot water pipes and electric bulbs.

The romance of ritual and colored emblem has been taken over

by that narrowest of all trades, modem art (the sort called art

for art's sake), and men are in modern practice informed that they

may use all symbols so long as they mean nothing by them.

The romance of conscience has been dried up into the science

of ethics; which may well be called decency for decency's sake,

decency unborn of cosmic energies and barren of artistic flower.

The cry to the dim gods, cut off from ethics and cosmology,

has become mere Psychical Research. Everything has been

sundered from everything else, and everything has grown cold.

Soon we shall hear of specialists dividing the tune from

the words of a song, on the ground that they spoil each other;

and I did once meet a man who openly advocated the separation

of almonds and raisins. This world is all one wild divorce court;

nevertheless, there are many who still hear in their souls

the thunder of authority of human habit; those whom Man hath

joined let no man sunder.

This book must avoid religion, but there must (I say)

be many, religious and irreligious, who will concede

that this power of answering many purposes was a sort

of strength which should not wholly die out of our lives.

As a part of personal character, even the moderns will agree that

many-sidedness is a merit and a merit that may easily be overlooked.

This balance and universality has been the vision of many groups

of men in many ages. It was the Liberal Education of Aristotle;

the jack-of-all-trades artistry of Leonardo da Vinci and his friends;

the august amateurishness of the Cavalier Person of Quality like

Sir William Temple or the great Earl of Dorset. It has appeared

in literature in our time in the most erratic and opposite shapes,

set to almost inaudible music by Walter Pater and enunciated

through a foghorn by Walt Whitman. But the great mass of men

have always been unable to achieve this literal universality,

because of the nature of their work in the world.

Not, let it be noted, because of the existence of their work.

Leonardo da Vinci must have worked pretty hard; on the other hand,

many a government office clerk, village constable or elusive

plumber may do (to all human appearance) no work at all,

and yet show no signs of the Aristotelian universalism.

What makes it difficult for the average man to be a

universalist is that the average man has to be a specialist;

he has not only to learn one trade, but to learn it so well

as to uphold him in a more or less ruthless society.

This is generally true of males from the first hunter to the last

electrical engineer; each has not merely to act, but to excel.

Nimrod has not only to be a mighty hunter before the Lord,

but also a mighty hunter before the other hunters.

The electrical engineer has to be a very electrical engineer,

or he is outstripped by engineers yet more electrical.

Those very miracles of the human mind on which the modern

world prides itself, and rightly in the main, would be

impossible without a certain concentration which disturbs

the pure balance of reason more than does religious bigotry.

No creed can be so limiting as that awful adjuration that

the cobbler must not go beyond his last. So the largest and

wildest shots of our world are but in one direction and with

a defined trajectory: the gunner cannot go beyond his shot,

and his shot so often falls short; the astronomer cannot go

beyond his telescope and his telescope goes such a little way.

All these are like men who have stood on the high peak of a mountain

and seen the horizon like a single ring and who then descend down

different paths towards different towns, traveling slow or fast.

It is right; there must be people traveling to different towns;

there must be specialists; but shall no one behold the horizon?

Shall all mankind be specialist surgeons or peculiar plumbers;

shall all humanity be monomaniac? Tradition has decided

that only half of humanity shall be monomaniac. It has decided

that in every home there shall be a tradesman and a Jack-of

all-trades. But it has also decided, among other things,

that the Jack of-all-trades shall be a Gill-of-all-trades. It

has decided, rightly or wrongly, that this specialism

and this universalism shall be divided between the sexes.

Cleverness shall be left for men and wisdom for women.

For cleverness kills wisdom; that is one of the few sad

and certain things.

But for women this ideal of comprehensive capacity (or common-sense)

must long ago have been washed away. It must have melted

in the frightful furnaces of ambition and eager technicality.

A man must be partly a one-idead man, because he is a

one-weaponed man--and he is flung naked into the fight.

The world's demand comes to him direct; to his wife indirectly.

In short, he must (as the books on Success say) give "his best";

and what a small part of a man "his best" is! His second

and third best are often much better. If he is the first violin

he must fiddle for life; he must not remember that he is

a fine fourth bagpipe, a fair fifteenth billiard-cue, a foil,

a fountain pen, a hand at whist, a gun, and an image of God.




III: THE EMANCIPATION OF DOMESTICITY

And it should be remarked in passing that this force upon a man to develop

one feature has nothing to do with what is commonly called our competitive

system, but would equally exist under any rationally conceivable kind

of Collectivism. Unless the Socialists are frankly ready for a fall

in the standard of violins, telescopes and electric lights, they must

somehow create a moral demand on the individual that he shall keep up

his present concentration on these things. It was only by men being

in some degree specialist that there ever were any telescopes; they must

certainly be in some degree specialist in order to keep them going.

It is not by making a man a State wage-earner that you can prevent him

thinking principally about the very difficult way he earns his wages.

There is only one way to preserve in the world that high levity and that

more leisurely outlook which fulfils the old vision of universalism.

That is, to permit the existence of a partly protected half of humanity;

a half which the harassing industrial demand troubles indeed, but only

troubles indirectly. In other words, there must be in every center

of humanity one human being upon a larger plan; one who does not "give

her best," but gives her all.

Our old analogy of the fire remains the most workable one.

The fire need not blaze like electricity nor boil like boiling water;

its point is that it blazes more than water and warms more than light.

The wife is like the fire, or to put things in their proper proportion,

the fire is like the wife. Like the fire, the woman is expected

to cook: not to excel in cooking, but to cook; to cook better

than her husband who is earning the coke by lecturing on botany

or breaking stones. Like the fire, the woman is expected to tell

tales to the children, not original and artistic tales, but tales--

better tales than would probably be told by a first-class cook.

Like the fire, the woman is expected to illuminate and ventilate,

not by the most startling revelations or the wildest winds of thought,

but better than a man can do it after breaking stones or lecturing.

But she cannot be expected to endure anything like this universal

duty if she is also to endure the direct cruelty of competitive or

bureaucratic toil. Woman must be a cook, but not a competitive cook;

a school mistress, but not a competitive schoolmistress;

a house-decorator but not a competitive house-decorator; a dressmaker,

but not a competitive dressmaker. She should have not one trade but

twenty hobbies; she, unlike the man, may develop all her second bests.

This is what has been really aimed at from the first in what

is called the seclusion, or even the oppression, of women.

Women were not kept at home in order to keep them narrow;

on the contrary, they were kept at home in order to keep them broad.

The world outside the home was one mass of narrowness,

a maze of cramped paths, a madhouse of monomaniacs.

It was only by partly limiting and protecting the woman that she

was enabled to play at five or six professions and so come almost

as near to God as the child when he plays at a hundred trades.

But the woman's professions, unlike the child's, were all truly

and almost terribly fruitful; so tragically real that nothing but

her universality and balance prevented them being merely morbid.

This is the substance of the contention I offer about the historic

female position. I do not deny that women have been wronged

and even tortured; but I doubt if they were ever tortured so much

as they are tortured now by the absurd modern attempt to make

them domestic empresses and competitive clerks at the same time.

I do not deny that even under the old tradition women had

a harder time than men; that is why we take off our hats.

I do not deny that all these various female functions were exasperating;

but I say that there was some aim and meaning in keeping them various.

I do not pause even to deny that woman was a servant; but at least

she was a general servant.

The shortest way of summarizing the position is to say that woman

stands for the idea of Sanity; that intellectual home to which

the mind must return after every excursion on extravagance.

The mind that finds its way to wild places is the poet's;

but the mind that never finds its way back is the lunatic's. There must

in every machine be a part that moves and a part that stands still;

there must be in everything that changes a part that is unchangeable.

And many of the phenomena which moderns hastily condemn are really parts

of this position of the woman as the center and pillar of health.

Much of what is called her subservience, and even her pliability,

is merely the subservience and pliability of a universal remedy;

she varies as medicines vary, with the disease. She has

to be an optimist to the morbid husband, a salutary pessimist

to the happy-go-lucky husband. She has to prevent the Quixote

from being put upon, and the bully from putting upon others.

The French King wrote--

"Toujours femme varie Bien fol qui s'y fie,"

but the truth is that woman always varies, and that is exactly why

we always trust her. To correct every adventure and extravagance

with its antidote in common-sense is not (as the moderns

seem to think) to be in the position of a spy or a slave.

It is to be in the position of Aristotle or (at the lowest)

Herbert Spencer, to be a universal morality, a complete system

of thought. The slave flatters; the complete moralist rebukes.

It is, in short, to be a Trimmer in the true sense of that honorable term;

which for some reason or other is always used in a sense exactly

opposite to its own. It seems really to be supposed that a Trimmer

means a cowardly person who always goes over to the stronger side.

It really means a highly chivalrous person who always goes over

to the weaker side; like one who trims a boat by sitting where there

are few people seated. Woman is a trimmer; and it is a generous,

dangerous and romantic trade.

The final fact which fixes this is a sufficiently plain one.

Supposing it to be conceded that humanity has acted at least

not unnaturally in dividing itself into two halves, respectively

typifying the ideals of special talent and of general sanity

(since they are genuinely difficult to combine completely in one

mind), it is not difficult to see why the line of cleavage has

followed the line of sex, or why the female became the emblem

of the universal and the male of the special and superior.

Two gigantic facts of nature fixed it thus: first, that the woman

who frequently fulfilled her functions literally could not be

specially prominent in experiment and adventure; and second,

that the same natural operation surrounded her with very young children,

who require to be taught not so much anything as everything.

Babies need not to be taught a trade, but to be introduced to a world.

To put the matter shortly, woman is generally shut up in a house

with a human being at the time when he asks all the questions

that there are, and some that there aren't. It would be odd

if she retained any of the narrowness of a specialist.

Now if anyone says that this duty of general enlightenment

(even when freed from modern rules and hours, and exercised

more spontaneously by a more protected person) is in itself

too exacting and oppressive, I can understand the view.

I can only answer that our race has thought it worth while to cast

this burden on women in order to keep common-sense in the world.

But when people begin to talk about this domestic duty as not merely

difficult but trivial and dreary, I simply give up the question.

For I cannot with the utmost energy of imagination conceive what

they mean. When domesticity, for instance, is called drudgery,

all the difficulty arises from a double meaning in the word.

If drudgery only means dreadfully hard work, I admit the woman

drudges in the home, as a man might drudge at the Cathedral of Amiens

or drudge behind a gun at Trafalgar. But if it means that the hard

work is more heavy because it is trifling, colorless and of small

import to the soul, then as I say, I give it up; I do not know

what the words mean. To be Queen Elizabeth within a definite area,

deciding sales, banquets, labors and holidays; to be Whiteley

within a certain area, providing toys, boots, sheets cakes.

and books, to be Aristotle within a certain area, teaching morals,

manners, theology, and hygiene; I can understand how this might

exhaust the mind, but I cannot imagine how it could narrow it.

How can it be a large career to tell other people's children about

the Rule of Three, and a small career to tell one's own children

about the universe? How can it be broad to be the same thing

to everyone, and narrow to be everything to someone? No; a woman's

function is laborious, but because it is gigantic, not because it

is minute I will pity Mrs. Jones for the hugeness of her task;

I will never pity her for its smallness.

But though the essential of the woman's task is universality,

this does not, of course, prevent her from having one or two severe

though largely wholesome prejudices. She has, on the whole,

been more conscious than man that she is only one half of humanity;

but she has expressed it (if one may say so of a lady) by getting her

teeth into the two or three things which she thinks she stands for.

I would observe here in parenthesis that much of the recent

official trouble about women has arisen from the fact that they

transfer to things of doubt and reason that sacred stubbornness

only proper to the primary things which a woman was set to guard.

One's own children, one's own altar, ought to be a matter of principle--

or if you like, a matter of prejudice. On the other hand,

who wrote Junius's Letters ought not to be a principle or a prejudice,

it ought to be a matter of free and almost indifferent inquiry.

But take an energetic modern girl secretary to a league

to show that George III wrote Junius, and in three months she

will believe it, too, out of mere loyalty to her employers.

Modern women defend their office with all the fierceness of domesticity.

They fight for desk and typewriter as for hearth and home, and develop

a sort of wolfish wifehood on behalf of the invisible head of the firm.

That is why they do office work so well; and that is why they ought

not to do it.




CHESTERTON-WHAT'S WRONG - III: THE COMMON VISION