CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - PATRIOTISM AND SPORT.


AN ESSAY ON TWO CITIES.

A little while ago I fell out of England into the town of Paris. If a

man fell out of the moon into the town of Paris he would know that it

was the capital of a great nation. If, however, he fell (perhaps off

some other side of the moon) so as to hit the city of London, he would

not know so well that it was the capital of a great nation; at any rate,

he would not know that the nation was so great as it is. This would be

so even on the assumption that the man from the moon could not read our

alphabet, as presumably he could not, unless elementary education in

that planet has gone to rather unsuspected lengths. But it is true that

a great part of the distinctive quality which separates Paris from

London may be even seen in the names. Real democrats always insist that

England is an aristocratic country. Real aristocrats always insist (for

some mysterious reason) that it is a democratic country. But if any one

has any real doubt about the matter let him consider simply the names of

the streets. Nearly all the streets out of the Strand, for instance, are

named after the first name, second name, third name, fourth, fifth, and

sixth names of some particular noble family; after their relations,

connections, or places of residence--Arundel Street, Norfolk Street,

Villiers Street, Bedford Street, Southampton Street, and any number of

others. The names are varied, so as to introduce the same family under

all sorts of different surnames. Thus we have Arundel Street and also

Norfolk Street; thus we have Buckingham Street and also Villiers Street.

To say that this is not aristocracy is simply intellectual impudence. I

am an ordinary citizen, and my name is Gilbert Keith Chesterton; and I

confess that if I found three streets in a row in the Strand, the first

called Gilbert Street, the second Keith Street, and the third Chesterton

Street, I should consider that I had become a somewhat more important

person in the commonwealth than was altogether good for its health. If

Frenchmen ran London (which God forbid!), they would think it quite as

ludicrous that those streets should be named after the Duke of

Buckingham as that they should be named after me. They are streets out

of one of the main thoroughfares of London. If French methods were

adopted, one of them would be called Shakspere Street, another Cromwell

Street, another Wordsworth Street; there would be statues of each of

these persons at the end of each of these streets, and any streets left

over would be named after the date on which the Reform Bill was passed

or the Penny Postage established.

Suppose a man tried to find people in London by the names of the places.

It would make a fine farce, illustrating our illogicality. Our hero

having once realised that Buckingham Street was named after the

Buckingham family, would naturally walk into Buckingham Palace in search

of the Duke of Buckingham. To his astonishment he would meet somebody

quite different. His simple lunar logic would lead him to suppose that

if he wanted the Duke of Marlborough (which seems unlikely) he would

find him at Marlborough House. He would find the Prince of Wales. When

at last he understood that the Marlboroughs live at Blenheim, named

after the great Marlborough's victory, he would, no doubt, go there. But

he would again find himself in error if, acting upon this principle, he

tried to find the Duke of Wellington, and told the cabman to drive to

Waterloo. I wonder that no one has written a wild romance about the

adventures of such an alien, seeking the great English aristocrats, and

only guided by the names; looking for the Duke of Bedford in the town of

that name, seeking for some trace of the Duke of Norfolk in Norfolk. He

might sail for Wellington in New Zealand to find the ancient seat of the

Wellingtons. The last scene might show him trying to learn Welsh in

order to converse with the Prince of Wales.

But even if the imaginary traveller knew no alphabet of this earth at

all, I think it would still be possible to suppose him seeing a

difference between London and Paris, and, upon the whole, the real

difference. He would not be able to read the words "Quai Voltaire;" but

he would see the sneering statue and the hard, straight roads; without

having heard of Voltaire he would understand that the city was

Voltairean. He would not know that Fleet Street was named after the

Fleet Prison. But the same national spirit which kept the Fleet Prison

closed and narrow still keeps Fleet Street closed and narrow. Or, if you

will, you may call Fleet Street cosy, and the Fleet Prison cosy. I think

I could be more comfortable in the Fleet Prison, in an English way of

comfort, than just under the statue of Voltaire. I think that the man

from the moon would know France without knowing French; I think that he

would know England without having heard the word. For in the last resort

all men talk by signs. To talk by statues is to talk by signs; to talk

by cities is to talk by signs. Pillars, palaces, cathedrals, temples,

pyramids, are an enormous dumb alphabet: as if some giant held up his

fingers of stone. The most important things at the last are always said

by signs, even if, like the Cross on St. Paul's, they are signs in

heaven. If men do not understand signs, they will never understand

words.

For my part, I should be inclined to suggest that the chief object of

education should be to restore simplicity. If you like to put it so, the

chief object of education is not to learn things; nay, the chief object

of education is to unlearn things. The chief object of education is to

unlearn all the weariness and wickedness of the world and to get back

into that state of exhilaration we all instinctively celebrate when we

write by preference of children and of boys. If I were an examiner

appointed to examine all examiners (which does not at present appear

probable), I would not only ask the teachers how much knowledge they had

imparted; I would ask them how much splendid and scornful ignorance they

had erected, like some royal tower in arms. But, in any case, I would

insist that people should have so much simplicity as would enable them

to see things suddenly and to see things as they are. I do not care so

much whether they can read the names over the shops. I do care very much

whether they can read the shops. I do not feel deeply troubled as to

whether they can tell where London is on the map so long as they can

tell where Brixton is on the way home. I do not even mind whether they

can put two and two together in the mathematical sense; I am content if

they can put two and two together in the metaphorical sense. But all

this longer statement of an obvious view comes back to the metaphor I

have employed. I do not care a dump whether they know the alphabet, so

long as they know the dumb alphabet.

Unfortunately, I have noticed in many aspects of our popular education

that this is not done at all. One teaches our London children to see

London with abrupt and simple eyes. And London is far more difficult to

see properly than any other place. London is a riddle. Paris is an

explanation. The education of the Parisian child is something

corresponding to the clear avenues and the exact squares of Paris. When

the Parisian boy has done learning about the French reason and the

Roman order he can go out and see the thing repeated in the shapes of

many shining public places, in the angles of many streets. But when the

English boy goes out, after learning about a vague progress and

idealism, he cannot see it anywhere. He cannot see anything anywhere,

except Sapolio and the Daily Mail. We must either alter London to suit

the ideals of our education, or else alter our education to suit the

great beauty of London.








FRENCH AND ENGLISH



It is obvious that there is a great deal of difference between being

international and being cosmopolitan. All good men are international.

Nearly all bad men are cosmopolitan. If we are to be international we

must be national. And it is largely because those who call themselves

the friends of peace have not dwelt sufficiently on this distinction

that they do not impress the bulk of any of the nations to which they

belong. International peace means a peace between nations, not a peace

after the destruction of nations, like the Buddhist peace after the

destruction of personality. The golden age of the good European is like

the heaven of the Christian: it is a place where people will love each

other; not like the heaven of the Hindu, a place where they will be each

other. And in the case of national character this can be seen in a

curious way. It will generally be found, I think, that the more a man

really appreciates and admires the soul of another people the less he

will attempt to imitate it; he will be conscious that there is something

in it too deep and too unmanageable to imitate. The Englishman who has a

fancy for France will try to be French; the Englishman who admires

France will remain obstinately English. This is to be particularly

noticed in the case of our relations with the French, because it is one

of the outstanding peculiarities of the French that their vices are all

on the surface, and their extraordinary virtues concealed. One might

almost say that their vices are the flower of their virtues.

Thus their obscenity is the expression of their passionate love of

dragging all things into the light. The avarice of their peasants means

the independence of their peasants. What the English call their rudeness

in the streets is a phase of their social equality. The worried look of

their women is connected with the responsibility of their women; and a

certain unconscious brutality of hurry and gesture in the men is related

to their inexhaustible and extraordinary military courage. Of all

countries, therefore, France is the worst country for a superficial fool

to admire. Let a fool hate France: if the fool loves it he will soon be

a knave. He will certainly admire it, not only for the things that are

not creditable, but actually for the things that are not there. He will

admire the grace and indolence of the most industrious people in the

world. He will admire the romance and fantasy of the most determinedly

respectable and commonplace people in the world. This mistake the

Englishman will make if he admires France too hastily; but the mistake

that he makes about France will be slight compared with the mistake that

he makes about himself. An Englishman who professes really to like

French realistic novels, really to be at home in a French modern

theatre, really to experience no shock on first seeing the savage French

caricatures, is making a mistake very dangerous for his own sincerity.

He is admiring something he does not understand. He is reaping where he

has not sown, and taking up where he has not laid down; he is trying to

taste the fruit when he has never toiled over the tree. He is trying to

pluck the exquisite fruit of French cynicism, when he has never tilled

the rude but rich soil of French virtue.

The thing can only be made clear to Englishmen by turning it round.

Suppose a Frenchman came out of democratic France to live in England,

where the shadow of the great houses still falls everywhere, and where

even freedom was, in its origin, aristocratic. If the Frenchman saw our

aristocracy and liked it, if he saw our snobbishness and liked it, if he

set himself to imitate it, we all know what we should feel. We all know

that we should feel that that particular Frenchman was a repulsive

little gnat. He would be imitating English aristocracy; he would be

imitating the English vice. But he would not even understand the vice he

plagiarised: especially he would not understand that the vice is partly

a virtue. He would not understand those elements in the English which

balance snobbishness and make it human: the great kindness of the

English, their hospitality, their unconscious poetry, their sentimental

conservatism, which really admires the gentry. The French Royalist sees

that the English like their King. But he does not grasp that while it is

base to worship a King, it is almost noble to worship a powerless King.

The impotence of the Hanoverian Sovereigns has raised the English loyal

subject almost to the chivalry and dignity of a Jacobite. The Frenchman

sees that the English servant is respectful: he does not realise that he

is also disrespectful; that there is an English legend of the humorous

and faithful servant, who is as much a personality as his master; the

Caleb Balderstone, the Sam Weller. He sees that the English do admire a

nobleman; he does not allow for the fact that they admire a nobleman

most when he does not behave like one. They like a noble to be

unconscious and amiable: the slave may be humble, but the master must

not be proud. The master is Life, as they would like to enjoy it; and

among the joys they desire in him there is none which they desire more

sincerely than that of generosity, of throwing money about among

mankind, or, to use the noble mediaeval word, largesse--the joy of

largeness. That is why a cabman tells you are no gentleman if you

give him his correct fare. Not only his pocket, but his soul is hurt.

You have wounded his ideal. You have defaced his vision of the perfect

aristocrat. All this is really very subtle and elusive; it is very

difficult to separate what is mere slavishness from what is a sort of

vicarious nobility in the English love of a lord. And no Frenchman

could easily grasp it at all. He would think it was mere slavishness;

and if he liked it, he would be a slave. So every Englishman must (at

first) feel French candour to be mere brutality. And if he likes it, he

is a brute. These national merits must not be understood so easily. It

requires long years of plenitude and quiet, the slow growth of great

parks, the seasoning of oaken beams, the dark enrichment of red wine in

cellars and in inns, all the leisure and the life of England through

many centuries, to produce at last the generous and genial fruit of

English snobbishness. And it requires battery and barricade, songs in

the streets, and ragged men dead for an idea, to produce and justify the

terrible flower of French indecency.

When I was in Paris a short time ago, I went with an English friend of

mine to an extremely brilliant and rapid succession of French plays,

each occupying about twenty minutes. They were all astonishingly

effective; but there was one of them which was so effective that my

friend and I fought about it outside, and had almost to be separated by

the police. It was intended to indicate how men really behaved in a

wreck or naval disaster, how they break down, how they scream, how they

fight each other without object and in a mere hatred of everything. And

then there was added, with all that horrible irony which Voltaire began,

a scene in which a great statesman made a speech over their bodies,

saying that they were all heroes and had died in a fraternal embrace. My

friend and I came out of this theatre, and as he had lived long in

Paris, he said, like a Frenchman: "What admirable artistic arrangement!

Is it not exquisite?" "No," I replied, assuming as far as possible the

traditional attitude of John Bull in the pictures in Punch--"No, it is

not exquisite. Perhaps it is unmeaning; if it is unmeaning I do not

mind. But if it has a meaning I know what the meaning is; it is that

under all their pageant of chivalry men are not only beasts, but even

hunted beasts. I do not know much of humanity, especially when humanity

talks in French. But I know when a thing is meant to uplift the human

soul, and when it is meant to depress it. I know that 'Cyrano de

Bergerac' (where the actors talked even quicker) was meant to encourage

man. And I know that this was meant to discourage him." "These

sentimental and moral views of art," began my friend, but I broke into

his words as a light broke into my mind. "Let me say to you," I said,

"what Jaures said to Liebknecht at the Socialist Conference: 'You have

not died on the barricades'. You are an Englishman, as I am, and you

ought to be as amiable as I am. These people have some right to be

terrible in art, for they have been terrible in politics. They may

endure mock tortures on the stage; they have seen real tortures in the

streets. They have been hurt for the idea of Democracy. They have been

hurt for the idea of Catholicism. It is not so utterly unnatural to them

that they should be hurt for the idea of literature. But, by blazes, it

is altogether unnatural to me! And the worst thing of all is that I, who

am an Englishman, loving comfort, should find comfort in such things as

this. The French do not seek comfort here, but rather unrest. This

restless people seeks to keep itself in a perpetual agony of the

revolutionary mood. Frenchmen, seeking revolution, may find the

humiliation of humanity inspiring. But God forbid that two

pleasure-seeking Englishmen should ever find it pleasant!"








THE ZOLA CONTROVERSY



The difference between two great nations can be illustrated by the

coincidence that at this moment both France and England are engaged in

discussing the memorial of a literary man. France is considering the

celebration of the late Zola, England is considering that of the

recently deceased Shakspere. There is some national significance, it may

be, in the time that has elapsed. Some will find impatience and

indelicacy in this early attack on Zola or deification of him; but the

nation which has sat still for three hundred years after Shakspere's

funeral may be considered, perhaps, to have carried delicacy too far.

But much deeper things are involved than the mere matter of time. The

point of the contrast is that the French are discussing whether there

shall be any monument, while the English are discussing only what the

monument shall be. In other words, the French are discussing a living

question, while we are discussing a dead one. Or rather, not a dead one,

but a settled one, which is quite a different thing.

When a thing of the intellect is settled it is not dead: rather it is

immortal. The multiplication table is immortal, and so is the fame of

Shakspere. But the fame of Zola is not dead or not immortal; it is at

its crisis, it is in the balance; and may be found wanting. The French,

therefore, are quite right in considering it a living question. It is

still living as a question, because it is not yet solved. But Shakspere

is not a living question: he is a living answer.

For my part, therefore, I think the French Zola controversy much more

practical and exciting than the English Shakspere one. The admission of

Zola to the Pantheon may be regarded as defining Zola's position. But

nobody could say that a statue of Shakspere, even fifty feet high, on

the top of St. Paul's Cathedral, could define Shakspere's position. It

only defines our position towards Shakspere. It is he who is fixed; it

is we who are unstable. The nearest approach to an English parallel to

the Zola case would be furnished if it were proposed to put some

savagely controversial and largely repulsive author among the ashes of

the greatest English poets. Suppose, for instance, it were proposed to

bury Mr. Rudyard Kipling in Westminster Abbey. I should be against

burying him in Westminster Abbey; first, because he is still alive (and

here I think even he himself might admit the justice of my protest); and

second, because I should like to reserve that rapidly narrowing space

for the great permanent examples, not for the interesting foreign

interruptions, of English literature. I would not have either Mr.

Kipling or Mr. George Moore in Westminster Abbey, though Mr. Kipling

has certainly caught even more cleverly than Mr. Moore the lucid and

cool cruelty of the French short story. I am very sure that Geoffrey

Chaucer and Joseph Addison get on very well together in the Poets'

Corner, despite the centuries that sunder them. But I feel that Mr.

George Moore would be much happier in Pere-la-Chaise, with a riotous

statue by Rodin on the top of him; and Mr. Kipling much happier under

some huge Asiatic monument, carved with all the cruelties of the gods.

As to the affair of the English monument to Shakspere, every people has

its own mode of commemoration, and I think there is a great deal to be

said for ours. There is the French monumental style, which consists in

erecting very pompous statues, very well done. There is the German

monumental style, which consists in erecting very pompous statues, badly

done. And there is the English monumental method, the great English way

with statues, which consists in not erecting them at all. A statue may

be dignified; but the absence of a statue is always dignified. For my

part, I feel there is something national, something wholesomely

symbolic, in the fact that there is no statue of Shakspere. There is, of

course, one in Leicester Square; but the very place where it stands

shows that it was put up by a foreigner for foreigners. There is surely

something modest and manly about not attempting to express our greatest

poet in the plastic arts in which we do not excel. We honour Shakspere

as the Jews honour God--by not daring to make of him a graven image. Our

sculpture, our statues, are good enough for bankers and

philanthropists, who are our curse: not good enough for him, who is our

benediction. Why should we celebrate the very art in which we triumph by

the very art in which we fail?

England is most easily understood as the country of amateurs. It is

especially the country of amateur soldiers (that is, of Volunteers), of

amateur statesmen (that is, of aristocrats), and it is not unreasonable

or out of keeping that it should be rather specially the country of a

careless and lounging view of literature. Shakspere has no academic

monument for the same reason that he had no academic education. He had

small Latin and less Greek, and (in the same spirit) he has never been

commemorated in Latin epitaphs or Greek marble. If there is nothing

clear and fixed about the emblems of his fame, it is because there was

nothing clear and fixed about the origins of it. Those great schools and

Universities which watch a man in his youth may record him in his death;

but Shakspere had no such unifying traditions. We can only say of him

what we can say of Dickens. We can only say that he came from nowhere

and that he went everywhere. For him a monument in any place is out of

place. A cold statue in a certain square is unsuitable to him as it

would be unsuitable to Dickens. If we put up a statue of Dickens in

Portland Place to-morrow we should feel the stiffness as unnatural. We

should fear that the statue might stroll about the street at night.

But in France the question of whether Zola shall go to the Pantheon when

he is dead is quite as practicable as the question whether he should go

to prison when he was alive. It is the problem of whether the nation

shall take one turn of thought or another. In raising a monument to Zola

they do not raise merely a trophy, but a finger-post. The question is

one which will have to be settled in most European countries; but like

all such questions, it has come first to a head in France; because

France is the battlefield of Christendom. That question is, of course,

roughly this: whether in that ill-defined area of verbal licence on

certain dangerous topics it is an extenuation of indelicacy or an

aggravation of it that the indelicacy was deliberate and solemn. Is

indecency more indecent if it is grave, or more indecent if it is gay?

For my part, I belong to an old school in this matter. When a book or a

play strikes me as a crime, I am not disarmed by being told that it is a

serious crime. If a man has written something vile, I am not comforted

by the explanation that he quite meant to do it. I know all the evils of

flippancy; I do not like the man who laughs at the sight of virtue. But

I prefer him to the man who weeps at the sight of virtue and complains

bitterly of there being any such thing. I am not reassured, when ethics

are as wild as cannibalism, by the fact that they are also as grave and

sincere as suicide. And I think there is an obvious fallacy in the

bitter contrasts drawn by some moderns between the aversion to Ibsen's

"Ghosts" and the popularity of some such joke as "Dear Old Charlie."

Surely there is nothing mysterious or unphilosophic in the popular

preference. The joke of "Dear Old Charlie" is passed--because it is a

joke. "Ghosts" are exorcised--because they are ghosts.

This is, of course, the whole question of Zola. I am grown up, and I do

not worry myself much about Zola's immorality. The thing I cannot stand

is his morality. If ever a man on this earth lived to embody the

tremendous text, "But if the light in your body be darkness, how great

is the darkness," it was certainly he. Great men like Ariosto, Rabelais,

and Shakspere fall in foul places, flounder in violent but venial sin,

sprawl for pages, exposing their gigantic weakness, are dirty, are

indefensible; and then they struggle up again and can still speak with a

convincing kindness and an unbroken honour of the best things in the

world: Rabelais, of the instruction of ardent and austere youth;

Ariosto, of holy chivalry; Shakspere, of the splendid stillness of

mercy. But in Zola even the ideals are undesirable; Zola's mercy is

colder than justice--nay, Zola's mercy is more bitter in the mouth than

injustice. When Zola shows us an ideal training he does not take us,

like Rabelais, into the happy fields of humanist learning. He takes us

into the schools of inhumanist learning, where there are neither books

nor flowers, nor wine nor wisdom, but only deformities in glass bottles,

and where the rule is taught from the exceptions. Zola's truth answers

the exact description of the skeleton in the cupboard; that is, it is

something of which a domestic custom forbids the discovery, but which is

quite dead, even when it is discovered. Macaulay said that the Puritans

hated bear-baiting, not because it gave pain to the bear, but because it

gave pleasure to the spectators. Of such substance also was this

Puritan who had lost his God. A Puritan of this type is worse than the

Puritan who hates pleasure because there is evil in it. This man

actually hates evil because there is pleasure in it. Zola was worse than

a pornographer, he was a pessimist. He did worse than encourage sin: he

encouraged discouragement. He made lust loathsome because to him lust

meant life.








OXFORD FROM WITHOUT



Some time ago I ventured to defend that race of hunted and persecuted

outlaws, the Bishops; but until this week I had no idea of how much

persecuted they were. For instance, the Bishop of Birmingham made some

extremely sensible remarks in the House of Lords, to the effect that

Oxford and Cambridge were (as everybody knows they are) far too much

merely plutocratic playgrounds. One would have thought that an Anglican

Bishop might be allowed to know something about the English University

system, and even to have, if anything, some bias in its favour. But (as

I pointed out) the rollicking Radicalism of Bishops has to be

restrained. The man who writes the notes in the weekly paper called the

Outlook feels that it is his business to restrain it. The passage has

such simple sublimity that I must quote it--

"Dr. Gore talked unworthily of his reputation when he spoke of the

older Universities as playgrounds for the rich and idle. In the first

place, the rich men there are not idle. Some of the rich men are, and so

are some of the poor men. On the whole, the sons of noble and wealthy

families keep up the best traditions of academic life."

So far this seems all very nice. It is a part of the universal principle

on which Englishmen have acted in recent years. As you will not try to

make the best people the most powerful people, persuade yourselves that

the most powerful people are the best people. Mad Frenchmen and Irishmen

try to realise the ideal. To you belongs the nobler (and much easier)

task of idealising the real. First give your Universities entirely into

the power of the rich; then let the rich start traditions; and then

congratulate yourselves on the fact that the sons of the rich keep up

these traditions. All that is quite simple and jolly. But then this

critic, who crushes Dr. Gore from the high throne of the Outlook, goes

on in a way that is really perplexing. "It is distinctly advantageous,"

he says, "that rich and poor--i. e., young men with a smooth path in

life before them, and those who have to hew out a road for

themselves--should be brought into association. Each class learns a

great deal from the other. On the one side, social conceit and

exclusiveness give way to the free spirit of competition amongst all

classes; on the other side, angularities and prejudices are rubbed

away." Even this I might have swallowed. But the paragraph concludes

with this extraordinary sentence: "We get the net result in such careers

as those of Lord Milner, Lord Curzon, and Mr. Asquith."

Those three names lay my intellect prostrate. The rest of the argument I

understand quite well. The social exclusiveness of aristocrats at Oxford

and Cambridge gives way before the free spirit of competition amongst

all classes. That is to say, there is at Oxford so hot and keen a

struggle, consisting of coal-heavers, London clerks, gypsies, navvies,

drapers' assistants, grocers' assistants--in short, all the classes that

make up the bulk of England--there is such a fierce competition at

Oxford among all these people that in its presence aristocratic

exclusiveness gives way. That is all quite clear. I am not quite sure

about the facts, but I quite understand the argument. But then, having

been called upon to contemplate this bracing picture of a boisterous

turmoil of all the classes of England, I am suddenly asked to accept as

example of it, Lord Milner, Lord Curzon, and the present Chancellor of

the Exchequer. What part do these gentlemen play in the mental process?

Is Lord Curzon one of the rugged and ragged poor men whose angularities

have been rubbed away? Or is he one of those whom Oxford immediately

deprived of all kind of social exclusiveness? His Oxford reputation does

not seem to bear out either account of him. To regard Lord Milner as a

typical product of Oxford would surely be unfair. It would be to deprive

the educational tradition of Germany of one of its most typical

products. English aristocrats have their faults, but they are not at all

like Lord Milner. What Mr. Asquith was meant to prove, whether he was a

rich man who lost his exclusiveness, or a poor man who lost his angles,

I am utterly unable to conceive.

There is, however, one mild but very evident truth that might perhaps be

mentioned. And it is this: that none of those three excellent persons

is, or ever has been, a poor man in the sense that that word is

understood by the overwhelming majority of the English nation. There are

no poor men at Oxford in the sense that the majority of men in the

street are poor. The very fact that the writer in the Outlook can talk

about such people as poor shows that he does not understand what the

modern problem is. His kind of poor man rather reminds me of the Earl in

the ballad by that great English satirist, Sir W.S. Gilbert, whose

angles (very acute angles) had, I fear, never been rubbed down by an old

English University. The reader will remember that when the

Periwinkle-girl was adored by two Dukes, the poet added--



"A third adorer had the girl,

A man of lowly station;

A miserable grovelling Earl

Besought her approbation."



Perhaps, indeed, some allusion to our University system, and to the

universal clash in it of all the classes of the community, may be found

in the verse a little farther on, which says--



"He'd had, it happily befell,

A decent education;

His views would have befitted well

A far superior station."



Possibly there was as simple a chasm between Lord Curzon and Lord

Milner. But I am afraid that the chasm will become almost imperceptible,

a microscopic crack, if we compare it with the chasm that separates

either or both of them from the people of this country.

Of course the truth is exactly as the Bishop of Birmingham put it. I am

sure that he did not put it in any unkindly or contemptuous spirit

towards those old English seats of learning, which whether they are or

are not seats of learning, are, at any rate, old and English, and those

are two very good things to be. The Old English University is a

playground for the governing class. That does not prove that it is a bad

thing; it might prove that it was a very good thing. Certainly if there

is a governing class, let there be a playground for the governing class.

I would much rather be ruled by men who know how to play than by men who

do not know how to play. Granted that we are to be governed by a rich

section of the community, it is certainly very important that that

section should be kept tolerably genial and jolly. If the sensitive man

on the Outlook does not like the phrase, "Playground of the rich," I

can suggest a phrase that describes such a place as Oxford perhaps with

more precision. It is a place for humanising those who might otherwise

be tyrants, or even experts.

To pretend that the aristocrat meets all classes at Oxford is too

ludicrous to be worth discussion. But it may be true that he meets more

different kinds of men than he would meet under a strictly aristocratic

regime of private tutors and small schools. It all comes back to the

fact that the English, if they were resolved to have an aristocracy,

were at least resolved to have a good-natured aristocracy. And it is due

to them to say that almost alone among the peoples of the world, they

have succeeded in getting one. One could almost tolerate the thing, if

it were not for the praise of it. One might endure Oxford, but not the

Outlook.

When the poor man at Oxford loses his angles (which means, I suppose,

his independence), he may perhaps, even if his poverty is of that highly

relative type possible at Oxford, gain a certain amount of worldly

advantage from the surrender of those angles. I must confess, however,

that I can imagine nothing nastier than to lose one's angles. It seems

to me that a desire to retain some angles about one's person is a desire

common to all those human beings who do not set their ultimate hopes

upon looking like Humpty-Dumpty. Our angles are simply our shapes. I

cannot imagine any phrase more full of the subtle and exquisite vileness

which is poisoning and weakening our country than such a phrase as this,

about the desirability of rubbing down the angularities of poor men.

Reduced to permanent and practical human speech, it means nothing

whatever except the corrupting of that first human sense of justice

which is the critic of all human institutions.

It is not in any such spirit of facile and reckless reassurance that we

should approach the really difficult problem of the delicate virtues and

the deep dangers of our two historic seats of learning. A good son does

not easily admit that his sick mother is dying; but neither does a good

son cheerily assert that she is "all right." There are many good

arguments for leaving the two historic Universities exactly as they are.

There are many good arguments for smashing them or altering them

entirely. But in either case the plain truth told by the Bishop of

Birmingham remains. If these Universities were destroyed, they would not

be destroyed as Universities. If they are preserved, they will not be

preserved as Universities. They will be preserved strictly and literally

as playgrounds; places valued for their hours of leisure more than for

their hours of work. I do not say that this is unreasonable; as a matter

of private temperament I find it attractive. It is not only possible to

say a great deal in praise of play; it is really possible to say the

highest things in praise of it. It might reasonably be maintained that

the true object of all human life is play. Earth is a task garden;

heaven is a playground. To be at last in such secure innocence that one

can juggle with the universe and the stars, to be so good that one can

treat everything as a joke--that may be, perhaps, the real end and final

holiday of human souls. When we are really holy we may regard the

Universe as a lark; so perhaps it is not essentially wrong to regard the

University as a lark. But the plain and present fact is that our upper

classes do regard the University as a lark, and do not regard it as a

University. It also happens very often that through some oversight they

neglect to provide themselves with that extreme degree of holiness which

I have postulated as a necessary preliminary to such indulgence in the

higher frivolity.

Humanity, always dreaming of a happy race, free, fantastic, and at

ease, has sometimes pictured them in some mystical island, sometimes in

some celestial city, sometimes as fairies, gods, or citizens of

Atlantis. But one method in which it has often indulged is to picture

them as aristocrats, as a special human class that could actually be

seen hunting in the woods or driving about the streets. And this never

was (as some silly Germans say) a worship of pride and scorn; mankind

never really admired pride; mankind never had any thing but a scorn for

scorn. It was a worship of the spectacle of happiness; especially of the

spectacle of youth. This is what the old Universities in their noblest

aspect really are; and this is why there is always something to be said

for keeping them as they are. Aristocracy is not a tyranny; it is not

even merely a spell. It is a vision. It is a deliberate indulgence in a

certain picture of pleasure painted for the purpose; every Duchess is

(in an innocent sense) painted, like Gainsborough's "Duchess of

Devonshire." She is only beautiful because, at the back of all, the

English people wanted her to be beautiful. In the same way, the lads at

Oxford and Cambridge are only larking because England, in the depths of

its solemn soul, really wishes them to lark. All this is very human and

pardonable, and would be even harmless if there were no such things in

the world as danger and honour and intellectual responsibility. But if

aristocracy is a vision, it is perhaps the most unpractical of all

visions. It is not a working way of doing things to put all your

happiest people on a lighted platform and stare only at them. It is not

a working way of managing education to be entirely content with the mere

fact that you have (to a degree unexampled in the world) given the

luckiest boys the jolliest time. It would be easy enough, like the

writer in the Outlook, to enjoy the pleasures and deny the perils. Oh

what a happy place England would be to live in if only one did not love

it!








CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - PATRIOTISM AND SPORT.