CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - OXFORD FROM WITHOUT


WOMAN



A correspondent has written me an able and interesting letter in the

matter of some allusions of mine to the subject of communal kitchens. He

defends communal kitchens very lucidly from the standpoint of the

calculating collectivist; but, like many of his school, he cannot

apparently grasp that there is another test of the whole matter, with

which such calculation has nothing at all to do. He knows it would be

cheaper if a number of us ate at the same time, so as to use the same

table. So it would. It would also be cheaper if a number of us slept at

different times, so as to use the same pair of trousers. But the

question is not how cheap are we buying a thing, but what are we buying?

It is cheap to own a slave. And it is cheaper still to be a slave.

My correspondent also says that the habit of dining out in restaurants,

etc., is growing. So, I believe, is the habit of committing suicide. I

do not desire to connect the two facts together. It seems fairly clear

that a man could not dine at a restaurant because he had just committed

suicide; and it would be extreme, perhaps, to suggest that he commits

suicide because he has just dined at a restaurant. But the two cases,

when put side by side, are enough to indicate the falsity and

poltroonery of this eternal modern argument from what is in fashion. The

question for brave men is not whether a certain thing is increasing; the

question is whether we are increasing it. I dine very often in

restaurants because the nature of my trade makes it convenient: but if I

thought that by dining in restaurants I was working for the creation of

communal meals, I would never enter a restaurant again; I would carry

bread and cheese in my pocket or eat chocolate out of automatic

machines. For the personal element in some things is sacred. I heard Mr.

Will Crooks put it perfectly the other day: "The most sacred thing is to

be able to shut your own door."

My correspondent says, "Would not our women be spared the drudgery of

cooking and all its attendant worries, leaving them free for higher

culture?" The first thing that occurs to me to say about this is very

simple, and is, I imagine, a part of all our experience. If my

correspondent can find any way of preventing women from worrying, he

will indeed be a remarkable man. I think the matter is a much deeper

one. First of all, my correspondent overlooks a distinction which is

elementary in our human nature. Theoretically, I suppose, every one would

like to be freed from worries. But nobody in the world would always

like to be freed from worrying occupations. I should very much like (as

far as my feelings at the moment go) to be free from the consuming

nuisance of writing this article. But it does not follow that I should

like to be free from the consuming nuisance of being a journalist.

Because we are worried about a thing, it does not follow that we are not

interested in it. The truth is the other way. If we are not interested,

why on earth should we be worried? Women are worried about housekeeping,

but those that are most interested are the most worried. Women are still

more worried about their husbands and their children. And I suppose if

we strangled the children and poleaxed the husbands it would leave women

free for higher culture. That is, it would leave them free to begin to

worry about that. For women would worry about higher culture as much as

they worry about everything else.

I believe this way of talking about women and their higher culture is

almost entirely a growth of the classes which (unlike the journalistic

class to which I belong) have always a reasonable amount of money. One

odd thing I specially notice. Those who write like this seem entirely to

forget the existence of the working and wage-earning classes. They say

eternally, like my correspondent, that the ordinary woman is always a

drudge. And what, in the name of the Nine Gods, is the ordinary man?

These people seem to think that the ordinary man is a Cabinet Minister.

They are always talking about man going forth to wield power, to carve

his own way, to stamp his individuality on the world, to command and to

be obeyed. This may be true of a certain class. Dukes, perhaps, are not

drudges; but, then, neither are Duchesses. The Ladies and Gentlemen of

the Smart Set are quite free for the higher culture, which consists

chiefly of motoring and Bridge. But the ordinary man who typifies and

constitutes the millions that make up our civilisation is no more free

for the higher culture than his wife is.

Indeed, he is not so free. Of the two sexes the woman is in the more

powerful position. For the average woman is at the head of something

with which she can do as she likes; the average man has to obey orders

and do nothing else. He has to put one dull brick on another dull brick,

and do nothing else; he has to add one dull figure to another dull

figure, and do nothing else. The woman's world is a small one, perhaps,

but she can alter it. The woman can tell the tradesman with whom she

deals some realistic things about himself. The clerk who does this to

the manager generally gets the sack, or shall we say (to avoid the

vulgarism), finds himself free for higher culture. Above all, as I said

in my previous article, the woman does work which is in some small

degree creative and individual. She can put the flowers or the furniture

in fancy arrangements of her own. I fear the bricklayer cannot put the

bricks in fancy arrangements of his own, without disaster to himself and

others. If the woman is only putting a patch into a carpet, she can

choose the thing with regard to colour. I fear it would not do for the

office boy dispatching a parcel to choose his stamps with a view to

colour; to prefer the tender mauve of the sixpenny to the crude scarlet

of the penny stamp. A woman cooking may not always cook artistically;

still she can cook artistically. She can introduce a personal and

imperceptible alteration into the composition of a soup. The clerk is

not encouraged to introduce a personal and imperceptible alteration into

the figures in a ledger.

The trouble is that the real question I raised is not discussed. It is

argued as a problem in pennies, not as a problem in people. It is not

the proposals of these reformers that I feel to be false so much as

their temper and their arguments. I am not nearly so certain that

communal kitchens are wrong as I am that the defenders of communal

kitchens are wrong. Of course, for one thing, there is a vast difference

between the communal kitchens of which I spoke and the communal meal

(monstrum horrendum, informe) which the darker and wilder mind of my

correspondent diabolically calls up. But in both the trouble is that

their defenders will not defend them humanly as human institutions. They

will not interest themselves in the staring psychological fact that

there are some things that a man or a woman, as the case may be, wishes

to do for himself or herself. He or she must do it inventively,

creatively, artistically, individually--in a word, badly. Choosing your

wife (say) is one of these things. Is choosing your husband's dinner one

of these things? That is the whole question: it is never asked.

And then the higher culture. I know that culture. I would not set any

man free for it if I could help it. The effect of it on the rich men who

are free for it is so horrible that it is worse than any of the other

amusements of the millionaire--worse than gambling, worse even than

philanthropy. It means thinking the smallest poet in Belgium greater

than the greatest poet of England. It means losing every democratic

sympathy. It means being unable to talk to a navvy about sport, or about

beer, or about the Bible, or about the Derby, or about patriotism, or

about anything whatever that he, the navvy, wants to talk about. It

means taking literature seriously, a very amateurish thing to do. It

means pardoning indecency only when it is gloomy indecency. Its

disciples will call a spade a spade; but only when it is a

grave-digger's spade. The higher culture is sad, cheap, impudent,

unkind, without honesty and without ease. In short, it is "high." That

abominable word (also applied to game) admirably describes it.

No; if you were setting women free for something else, I might be more

melted. If you can assure me, privately and gravely, that you are

setting women free to dance on the mountains like maenads, or to worship

some monstrous goddess, I will make a note of your request. If you are

quite sure that the ladies in Brixton, the moment they give up cooking,

will beat great gongs and blow horns to Mumbo-Jumbo, then I will agree

that the occupation is at least human and is more or less entertaining.

Women have been set free to be Bacchantes; they have been set free to be

Virgin Martyrs; they have been set free to be Witches. Do not ask them

now to sink so low as the higher culture.

I have my own little notions of the possible emancipation of women; but

I suppose I should not be taken very seriously if I propounded them. I

should favour anything that would increase the present enormous

authority of women and their creative action in their own homes. The

average woman, as I have said, is a despot; the average man is a serf. I

am for any scheme that any one can suggest that will make the average

woman more of a despot. So far from wishing her to get her cooked meals

from outside, I should like her to cook more wildly and at her own will

than she does. So far from getting always the same meals from the same

place, let her invent, if she likes, a new dish every day of her life.

Let woman be more of a maker, not less. We are right to talk about

"Woman;" only blackguards talk about women. Yet all men talk about men,

and that is the whole difference. Men represent the deliberative and

democratic element in life. Woman represents the despotic.








THE MODERN MARTYR



The incident of the Suffragettes who chained themselves with iron chains

to the railings of Downing Street is a good ironical allegory of most

modern martyrdom. It generally consists of a man chaining himself up and

then complaining that he is not free. Some say that such larks retard

the cause of female suffrage, others say that such larks alone can

advance it; as a matter of fact, I do not believe that they have the

smallest effect one way or the other.

The modern notion of impressing the public by a mere demonstration of

unpopularity, by being thrown out of meetings or thrown into jail is

largely a mistake. It rests on a fallacy touching the true popular value

of martyrdom. People look at human history and see that it has often

happened that persecutions have not only advertised but even advanced a

persecuted creed, and given to its validity the public and dreadful

witness of dying men. The paradox was pictorially expressed in Christian

art, in which saints were shown brandishing as weapons the very tools

that had slain them. And because his martyrdom is thus a power to the

martyr, modern people think that any one who makes himself slightly

uncomfortable in public will immediately be uproariously popular. This

element of inadequate martyrdom is not true only of the Suffragettes; it

is true of many movements I respect and some that I agree with. It was

true, for instance, of the Passive Resisters, who had pieces of their

furniture sold up. The assumption is that if you show your ordinary

sincerity (or even your political ambition) by being a nuisance to

yourself as well as to other people, you will have the strength of the

great saints who passed through the fire. Any one who can be hustled in

a hall for five minutes, or put in a cell for five days, has achieved

what was meant by martyrdom, and has a halo in the Christian art of the

future. Miss Pankhurst will be represented holding a policeman in each

hand--the instruments of her martyrdom. The Passive Resister will be

shown symbolically carrying the teapot that was torn from him by

tyrannical auctioneers.

But there is a fallacy in this analogy of martyrdom. The truth is that

the special impressiveness which does come from being persecuted only

happens in the case of extreme persecution. For the fact that the modern

enthusiast will undergo some inconvenience for the creed he holds only

proves that he does hold it, which no one ever doubted. No one doubts

that the Nonconformist minister cares more for Nonconformity than he

does for his teapot. No one doubts that Miss Pankhurst wants a vote more

than she wants a quiet afternoon and an armchair. All our ordinary

intellectual opinions are worth a bit of a row: I remember during the

Boer War fighting an Imperialist clerk outside the Queen's Hall, and

giving and receiving a bloody nose; but I did not think it one of the

incidents that produce the psychological effect of the Roman

amphitheatre or the stake at Smithfield. For in that impression there is

something more than the mere fact that a man is sincere enough to give

his time or his comfort. Pagans were not impressed by the torture of

Christians merely because it showed that they honestly held their

opinion; they knew that millions of people honestly held all sorts of

opinions. The point of such extreme martyrdom is much more subtle. It is

that it gives an appearance of a man having something quite specially

strong to back him up, of his drawing upon some power. And this can only

be proved when all his physical contentment is destroyed; when all the

current of his bodily being is reversed and turned to pain. If a man is

seen to be roaring with laughter all the time that he is skinned alive,

it would not be unreasonable to deduce that somewhere in the recesses of

his mind he had thought of a rather good joke. Similarly, if men smiled

and sang (as they did) while they were being boiled or torn in pieces,

the spectators felt the presence of something more than mere mental

honesty: they felt the presence of some new and unintelligible kind of

pleasure, which, presumably, came from somewhere. It might be a strength

of madness, or a lying spirit from Hell; but it was something quite

positive and extraordinary; as positive as brandy and as extraordinary

as conjuring. The Pagan said to himself: "If Christianity makes a man

happy while his legs are being eaten by a lion, might it not make me

happy while my legs are still attached to me and walking down the

street?" The Secularists laboriously explain that martyrdoms do not

prove a faith to be true, as if anybody was ever such a fool as to

suppose that they did. What they did prove, or, rather, strongly

suggest, was that something had entered human psychology which was

stronger than strong pain. If a young girl, scourged and bleeding to

death, saw nothing but a crown descending on her from God, the first

mental step was not that her philosophy was correct, but that she was

certainly feeding on something. But this particular point of psychology

does not arise at all in the modern cases of mere public discomfort or

inconvenience. The causes of Miss Pankhurst's cheerfulness require no

mystical explanations. If she were being burned alive as a witch, if she

then looked up in unmixed rapture and saw a ballot-box descending out of

heaven, then I should say that the incident, though not conclusive, was

frightfully impressive. It would not prove logically that she ought to

have the vote, or that anybody ought to have the vote. But it would

prove this: that there was, for some reason, a sacramental reality in

the vote, that the soul could take the vote and feed on it; that it was

in itself a positive and overpowering pleasure, capable of being pitted

against positive and overpowering pain.

I should advise modern agitators, therefore, to give up this particular

method: the method of making very big efforts to get a very small

punishment. It does not really go down at all; the punishment is too

small, and the efforts are too obvious. It has not any of the

effectiveness of the old savage martyrdom, because it does not leave the

victim absolutely alone with his cause, so that his cause alone can

support him. At the same time it has about it that element of the

pantomimic and the absurd, which was the cruellest part of the slaying

and the mocking of the real prophets. St. Peter was crucified upside

down as a huge inhuman joke; but his human seriousness survived the

inhuman joke, because, in whatever posture, he had died for his faith.

The modern martyr of the Pankhurst type courts the absurdity without

making the suffering strong enough to eclipse the absurdity. She is like

a St. Peter who should deliberately stand on his head for ten seconds

and then expect to be canonised for it.

Or, again, the matter might be put in this way. Modern martyrdoms fail

even as demonstrations, because they do not prove even that the martyrs

are completely serious. I think, as a fact, that the modern martyrs

generally are serious, perhaps a trifle too serious. But their martyrdom

does not prove it; and the public does not always believe it.

Undoubtedly, as a fact, Dr. Clifford is quite honourably indignant with

what he considers to be clericalism, but he does not prove it by having

his teapot sold; for a man might easily have his teapot sold as an

actress has her diamonds stolen--as a personal advertisement. As a

matter of fact, Miss Pankhurst is quite in earnest about votes for

women. But she does not prove it by being chucked out of meetings. A

person might be chucked out of meetings just as young men are chucked

out of music-halls--for fun. But no man has himself eaten by a lion as a

personal advertisement. No woman is broiled on a gridiron for fun. That

is where the testimony of St. Perpetua and St. Faith comes in. Doubtless

it is no fault of these enthusiasts that they are not subjected to the

old and searching penalties; very likely they would pass through them as

triumphantly as St. Agatha. I am simply advising them upon a point of

policy, things being as they are. And I say that the average man is not

impressed with their sacrifices simply because they are not and cannot

be more decisive than the sacrifices which the average man himself would

make for mere fun if he were drunk. Drunkards would interrupt meetings

and take the consequences. And as for selling a teapot, it is an act, I

imagine, in which any properly constituted drunkard would take a

positive pleasure. The advertisement is not good enough; it does not

tell. If I were really martyred for an opinion (which is more improbable

than words can say), it would certainly only be for one or two of my

most central and sacred opinions. I might, perhaps, be shot for England,

but certainly not for the British Empire. I might conceivably die for

political freedom, but I certainly wouldn't die for Free Trade. But as

for kicking up the particular kind of shindy that the Suffragettes are

kicking up, I would as soon do it for my shallowest opinion as for my

deepest one. It never could be anything worse than an inconvenience; it

never could be anything better than a spree. Hence the British public,

and especially the working classes, regard the whole demonstration with

fundamental indifference; for, while it is a demonstration that probably

is adopted from the most fanatical motives, it is a demonstration which

might be adopted from the most frivolous.








ON POLITICAL SECRECY



Generally, instinctively, in the absence of any special reason, humanity

hates the idea of anything being hidden--that is, it hates the idea of

anything being successfully hidden. Hide-and-seek is a popular pastime;

but it assumes the truth of the text, "Seek and ye shall find."

Ordinary mankind (gigantic and unconquerable in its power of joy) can

get a great deal of pleasure out of a game called "hide the thimble,"

but that is only because it is really a game of "see the thimble."

Suppose that at the end of such a game the thimble had not been found at

all; suppose its place was unknown for ever: the result on the players

would not be playful, it would be tragic. That thimble would hag-ride

all their dreams. They would all die in asylums. The pleasure is all in

the poignant moment of passing from not knowing to knowing. Mystery

stories are very popular, especially when sold at sixpence; but that is

because the author of a mystery story reveals. He is enjoyed not because

he creates mystery, but because he destroys mystery. Nobody would have

the courage to publish a detective-story which left the problem exactly

where it found it. That would rouse even the London public to

revolution. No one dare publish a detective-story that did not detect.

There are three broad classes of the special things in which human

wisdom does permit privacy. The first is the case I have mentioned--that

of hide-and-seek, or the police novel, in which it permits privacy only

in order to explode and smash privacy. The author makes first a

fastidious secret of how the Bishop was murdered, only in order that he

may at last declare, as from a high tower, to the whole democracy the

great glad news that he was murdered by the governess. In that case,

ignorance is only valued because being ignorant is the best and purest

preparation for receiving the horrible revelations of high life.

Somewhat in the same way being an agnostic is the best and purest

preparation for receiving the happy revelations of St. John.

This first sort of secrecy we may dismiss, for its whole ultimate object

is not to keep the secret, but to tell it. Then there is a second and

far more important class of things which humanity does agree to hide.

They are so important that they cannot possibly be discussed here. But

every one will know the kind of things I mean. In connection with these,

I wish to remark that though they are, in one sense, a secret, they are

also always a "secret de Polichinelle." Upon sex and such matters we are

in a human freemasonry; the freemasonry is disciplined, but the

freemasonry is free. We are asked to be silent about these things, but

we are not asked to be ignorant about them. On the contrary, the

fundamental human argument is entirely the other way. It is the thing

most common to humanity that is most veiled by humanity. It is exactly

because we all know that it is there that we need not say that it is

there.

Then there is a third class of things on which the best civilisation

does permit privacy, does resent all inquiry or explanation. This is in

the case of things which need not be explained, because they cannot be

explained, things too airy, instinctive, or intangible--caprices, sudden

impulses, and the more innocent kind of prejudice. A man must not be

asked why he is talkative or silent, for the simple reason that he does

not know. A man is not asked (even in Germany) why he walks slow or

quick, simply because he could not answer. A man must take his own road

through a wood, and make his own use of a holiday. And the reason is

this: not because he has a strong reason, but actually because he has a

weak reason; because he has a slight and fleeting feeling about the

matter which he could not explain to a policeman, which perhaps the very

appearance of a policeman out of the bushes might destroy. He must act

on the impulse, because the impulse is unimportant, and he may never

have the same impulse again. If you like to put it so he must act on the

impulse because the impulse is not worth a moment's thought. All these

fancies men feel should be private; and even Fabians have never proposed

to interfere with them.

Now, for the last fortnight the newspapers have been full of very varied

comments upon the problem of the secrecy of certain parts of our

political finance, and especially of the problem of the party funds.

Some papers have failed entirely to understand what the quarrel is

about. They have urged that Irish members and Labour members are also

under the shadow, or, as some have said, even more under it. The ground

of this frantic statement seems, when patiently considered, to be simply

this: that Irish and Labour members receive money for what they do. All

persons, as far as I know, on this earth receive money for what they do;

the only difference is that some people, like the Irish members, do it.

I cannot imagine that any human being could think any other human being

capable of maintaining the proposition that men ought not to receive

money. The simple point is that, as we know that some money is given

rightly and some wrongly, an elementary common-sense leads us to look

with indifference at the money that is given in the middle of Ludgate

Circus, and to look with particular suspicion at the money which a man

will not give unless he is shut up in a box or a bathing-machine. In

short, it is too silly to suppose that anybody could ever have discussed

the desirability of funds. The only thing that even idiots could ever

have discussed is the concealment of funds. Therefore, the whole

question that we have to consider is whether the concealment of

political money-transactions, the purchase of peerages, the payment of

election expenses, is a kind of concealment that falls under any of the

three classes I have mentioned as those in which human custom and

instinct does permit us to conceal. I have suggested three kinds of

secrecy which are human and defensible. Can this institution be defended

by means of any of them?

Now the question is whether this political secrecy is of any of the

kinds that can be called legitimate. We have roughly divided legitimate

secrets into three classes. First comes the secret that is only kept in

order to be revealed, as in the detective stories; secondly, the secret

which is kept because everybody knows it, as in sex; and third, the

secret which is kept because it is too delicate and vague to be

explained at all, as in the choice of a country walk. Do any of these

broad human divisions cover such a case as that of secrecy of the

political and party finances? It would be absurd, and even delightfully

absurd, to pretend that any of them did. It would be a wild and charming

fancy to suggest that our politicians keep political secrets only that

they may make political revelations. A modern peer only pretends that he

has earned his peerage in order that he may more dramatically declare,

with a scream of scorn and joy, that he really bought it. The Baronet

pretends that he deserved his title only in order to make more exquisite

and startling the grand historical fact that he did not deserve it.

Surely this sounds improbable. Surely all our statesmen cannot be saving

themselves up for the excitement of a death-bed repentance. The writer

of detective tales makes a man a duke solely in order to blast him with

a charge of burglary. But surely the Prime Minister does not make a man

a duke solely in order to blast him with a charge of bribery. No; the

detective-tale theory of the secrecy of political funds must (with a

sigh) be given up.

Neither can we say that the thing is explained by that second case of

human secrecy which is so secret that it is hard to discuss it in

public. A decency is preserved about certain primary human matters

precisely because every one knows all about them. But the decency

touching contributions, purchases, and peerages is not kept up because

most ordinary men know what is happening; it is kept up precisely

because most ordinary men do not know what is happening. The ordinary

curtain of decorum covers normal proceedings. But no one will say that

being bribed is a normal proceeding.

And if we apply the third test to this problem of political secrecy, the

case is even clearer and even more funny. Surely no one will say that

the purchase of peerages and such things are kept secret because they

are so light and impulsive and unimportant that they must be matters of

individual fancy. A child sees a flower and for the first time feels

inclined to pick it. But surely no one will say that a brewer sees a

coronet and for the first time suddenly thinks that he would like to be

a peer. The child's impulse need not be explained to the police, for the

simple reason that it could not be explained to anybody. But does any

one believe that the laborious political ambitions of modern commercial

men ever have this airy and incommunicable character? A man lying on the

beach may throw stones into the sea without any particular reason. But

does any one believe that the brewer throws bags of gold into the party

funds without any particular reason? This theory of the secrecy of

political money must also be regretfully abandoned; and with it the two

other possible excuses as well. This secrecy is one which cannot be

justified as a sensational joke nor as a common human freemasonry, nor

as an indescribable personal whim. Strangely enough, indeed, it violates

all three conditions and classes at once. It is not hidden in order to

be revealed: it is hidden in order to be hidden. It is not kept secret

because it is a common secret of mankind, but because mankind must not

get hold of it. And it is not kept secret because it is too unimportant

to be told, but because it is much too important to bear telling. In

short, the thing we have is the real and perhaps rare political

phenomenon of an occult government. We have an exoteric and an esoteric

doctrine. England is really ruled by priestcraft, but not by priests. We

have in this country all that has ever been alleged against the evil

side of religion; the peculiar class with privileges, the sacred words

that are unpronounceable; the important things known only to the few. In

fact we lack nothing except the religion.

* * * * *




EDWARD VII. AND SCOTLAND

I have received a serious, and to me, at any rate, an impressive

remonstrance from the Scottish Patriotic Association. It appears that I

recently referred to Edward VII. of Great Britain and Ireland, King,

Defender of the Faith, under the horrible description of the King of

England. The Scottish Patriotic Association draws my attention to the

fact that by the provisions of the Act of Union, and the tradition of

nationality, the monarch should be referred to as the King of Britain.

The blow thus struck at me is particularly wounding because it is

particularly unjust. I believe in the reality of the independent

nationalities under the British Crown much more passionately and

positively than any other educated Englishman of my acquaintance

believes in it. I am quite certain that Scotland is a nation; I am quite

certain that nationality is the key of Scotland; I am quite certain that

all our success with Scotland has been due to the fact that we have in

spirit treated it as a nation. I am quite certain that Ireland is a

nation; I am quite certain that nationality is the key to Ireland; I am

quite certain that all our failure in Ireland arose from the fact that

we would not in spirit treat it as a nation. It would be difficult to

find, even among the innumerable examples that exist, a stronger example

of the immensely superior importance of sentiment to what is called

practicality than this case of the two sister nations. It is not that we

have encouraged a Scotchman to be rich; it is not that we have

encouraged a Scotchman to be active; it is not that we have encouraged a

Scotchman to be free. It is that we have quite definitely encouraged a

Scotchman to be Scotch.

A vague, but vivid impression was received from all our writers of

history, philosophy, and rhetoric that the Scottish element was

something really valuable in itself, was something which even Englishmen

were forced to recognise and respect. If we ever admitted the beauty of

Ireland, it was as something which might be loved by an Englishman but

which could hardly be respected even by an Irishman. A Scotchman might

be proud of Scotland; it was enough for an Irishman that he could be

fond of Ireland. Our success with the two nations has been exactly

proportioned to our encouragement of their independent national

emotion; the one that we would not treat nationally has alone produced

Nationalists. The one nation that we would not recognise as a nation in

theory is the one that we have been forced to recognise as a nation in

arms. The Scottish Patriotic Association has no need to draw my

attention to the importance of the separate national sentiment or the

need of keeping the Border as a sacred line. The case is quite

sufficiently proved by the positive history of Scotland. The place of

Scottish loyalty to England has been taken by English admiration of

Scotland. They do not need to envy us our titular leadership, when we

seem to envy them their separation.

I wish to make very clear my entire sympathy with the national sentiment

of the Scottish Patriotic Association. But I wish also to make clear

this very enlightening comparison between the fate of Scotch and of

Irish patriotism. In life it is always the little facts that express the

large emotions, and if the English once respected Ireland as they

respect Scotland, it would come out in a hundred small ways. For

instance, there are crack regiments in the British Army which wear the

kilt--the kilt which, as Macaulay says with perfect truth, was regarded

by nine Scotchmen out of ten as the dress of a thief. The Highland

officers carry a silver-hilted version of the old barbarous Gaelic

broadsword with a basket-hilt, which split the skulls of so many English

soldiers at Killiecrankie and Prestonpans. When you have a regiment of

men in the British Army carrying ornamental silver shillelaghs you will

have done the same thing for Ireland, and not before--or when you

mention Brian Boru with the same intonation as Bruce.

Let me be considered therefore to have made quite clear that I believe

with a quite special intensity in the independent consideration of

Scotland and Ireland as apart from England. I believe that, in the

proper sense of the words, Scotland is an independent nation, even if

Edward VII. is the King of Scotland. I believe that, in the proper sense

of words, Ireland is an independent nation, even if Edward VII. is King

of Ireland. But the fact is that I have an even bolder and wilder belief

than either of these. I believe that England is an independent nation. I

believe that England also has its independent colour and history, and

meaning. I believe that England could produce costumes quite as queer as

the kilt; I believe that England has heroes fully as untranslateable as

Brian Boru, and consequently I believe that Edward VII. is, among his

innumerable other functions, really King of England. If my Scotch

friends insist, let us call it one of his quite obscure, unpopular, and

minor titles; one of his relaxations. A little while ago he was Duke of

Cornwall; but for a family accident he might still have been King of

Hanover. Nor do I think that we should blame the simple Cornishmen if

they spoke of him in a rhetorical moment by his Cornish title, nor the

well-meaning Hanoverians if they classed him with Hanoverian Princes.

Now it so happens that in the passage complained of I said the King of

England merely because I meant the King of England. I was speaking

strictly and especially of English Kings, of Kings in the tradition of

the old Kings of England. I wrote as an English nationalist keenly

conscious of the sacred boundary of the Tweed that keeps (or used to

keep) our ancient enemies at bay. I wrote as an English nationalist

resolved for one wild moment to throw off the tyranny of the Scotch and

Irish who govern and oppress my country. I felt that England was at

least spiritually guarded against these surrounding nationalities. I

dreamed that the Tweed was guarded by the ghosts of Scropes and Percys;

I dreamed that St. George's Channel was guarded by St. George. And in

this insular security I spoke deliberately and specifically of the King

of England, of the representative of the Tudors and Plantagenets. It is

true that the two Kings of England, of whom I especially spoke, Charles

II. and George III., had both an alien origin, not very recent and not

very remote. Charles II. came of a family originally Scotch. George III.

came of a family originally German. But the same, so far as that goes,

could be said of the English royal houses when England stood quite

alone. The Plantagenets were originally a French family. The Tudors were

originally a Welsh family. But I was not talking of the amount of

English sentiment in the English Kings. I was talking of the amount of

English sentiment in the English treatment and popularity of the English

Kings. With that Ireland and Scotland have nothing whatever to do.

Charles II. may, for all I know, have not only been King of Scotland; he

may, by virtue of his temper and ancestry, have been a Scotch King of

Scotland. There was something Scotch about his combination of

clear-headedness with sensuality. There was something Scotch about his

combination of doing what he liked with knowing what he was doing. But I

was not talking of the personality of Charles, which may have been

Scotch. I was talking of the popularity of Charles, which was certainly

English. One thing is quite certain: whether or no he ever ceased to be

a Scotch man, he ceased as soon as he conveniently could to be a Scotch

King. He had actually tried the experiment of being a national ruler

north of the Tweed, and his people liked him as little as he liked them.

Of Presbyterianism, of the Scottish religion, he left on record the

exquisitely English judgment that it was "no religion for a gentleman."

His popularity then was purely English; his royalty was purely English;

and I was using the words with the utmost narrowness and deliberation

when I spoke of this particular popularity and royalty as the popularity

and royalty of a King of England. I said of the English people specially

that they like to pick up the King's crown when he has dropped it. I do

not feel at all sure that this does apply to the Scotch or the Irish. I

think that the Irish would knock his crown off for him. I think that the

Scotch would keep it for him after they had picked it up.

For my part, I should be inclined to adopt quite the opposite method of

asserting nationality. Why should good Scotch nationalists call Edward

VII. the King of Britain? They ought to call him King Edward I. of

Scotland. What is Britain? Where is Britain? There is no such place.

There never was a nation of Britain; there never was a King of Britain;

unless perhaps Vortigern or Uther Pendragon had a taste for the title.

If we are to develop our Monarchy, I should be altogether in favour of

developing it along the line of local patriotism and of local

proprietorship in the King. I think that the Londoners ought to call him

the King of London, and the Liverpudlians ought to call him the King of

Liverpool. I do not go so far as to say that the people of Birmingham

ought to call Edward VII. the King of Birmingham; for that would be high

treason to a holier and more established power. But I think we might

read in the papers: "The King of Brighton left Brighton at half-past two

this afternoon," and then immediately afterwards, "The King of Worthing

entered Worthing at ten minutes past three." Or, "The people of Margate

bade a reluctant farewell to the popular King of Margate this morning,"

and then, "His Majesty the King of Ramsgate returned to his country and

capital this afternoon after his long sojourn in strange lands." It

might be pointed out that by a curious coincidence the departure of the

King of Oxford occurred a very short time before the triumphal arrival

of the King of Reading. I cannot imagine any method which would more

increase the kindly and normal relations between the Sovereign and his

people. Nor do I think that such a method would be in any sense a

depreciation of the royal dignity; for, as a matter of fact, it would

put the King upon the same platform with the gods. The saints, the most

exalted of human figures, were also the most local. It was exactly the

men whom we most easily connected with heaven whom we also most easily

connected with earth.








CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - OXFORD FROM WITHOUT