CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - EDWARD VII. AND SCOTLAND


THOUGHTS AROUND KOEPENICK



A famous and epigrammatic author said that life copied literature; it

seems clear that life really caricatures it. I suggested recently that

the Germans submitted to, and even admired, a solemn and theatrical

assertion of authority. A few hours after I had sent up my "copy," I saw

the first announcement of the affair of the comic Captain at Koepenick.

The most absurd part of this absurd fraud (at least, to English eyes) is

one which, oddly enough, has received comparatively little comment. I

mean the point at which the Mayor asked for a warrant, and the Captain

pointed to the bayonets of his soldiery and said. "These are my

authority." One would have thought any one would have known that no

soldier would talk like that. The dupes were blamed for not knowing that

the man wore the wrong cap or the wrong sash, or had his sword buckled

on the wrong way; but these are technicalities which they might surely

be excused for not knowing. I certainly should not know if a soldier's

sash were on inside out or his cap on behind before. But I should know

uncommonly well that genuine professional soldiers do not talk like

Adelphi villains and utter theatrical epigrams in praise of abstract

violence.

We can see this more clearly, perhaps, if we suppose it to be the case

of any other dignified and clearly distinguishable profession. Suppose a

Bishop called upon me. My great modesty and my rather distant reverence

for the higher clergy might lead me certainly to a strong suspicion that

any Bishop who called on me was a bogus Bishop. But if I wished to test

his genuineness I should not dream of attempting to do so by examining

the shape of his apron or the way his gaiters were done up. I have not

the remotest idea of the way his gaiters ought to be done up. A very

vague approximation to an apron would probably take me in; and if he

behaved like an approximately Christian gentleman he would be safe

enough from my detection. But suppose the Bishop, the moment he entered

the room, fell on his knees on the mat, clasped his hands, and poured

out a flood of passionate and somewhat hysterical extempore prayer, I

should say at once and without the smallest hesitation, "Whatever else

this man is, he is not an elderly and wealthy cleric of the Church of

England. They don't do such things." Or suppose a man came to me

pretending to be a qualified doctor, and flourished a stethoscope, or

what he said was a stethoscope. I am glad to say that I have not even

the remotest notion of what a stethoscope looks like; so that if he

flourished a musical-box or a coffee-mill it would be all one to me. But

I do think that I am not exaggerating my own sagacity if I say that I

should begin to suspect the doctor if on entering my room he flung his

legs and arms about, crying wildly, "Health! Health! priceless gift of

Nature! I possess it! I overflow with it! I yearn to impart it! Oh, the

sacred rapture of imparting health!" In that case I should suspect him

of being rather in a position to receive than to offer medical

superintendence.

Now, it is no exaggeration at all to say that any one who has ever known

any soldiers (I can only answer for English and Irish and Scotch

soldiers) would find it just as easy to believe that a real Bishop would

grovel on the carpet in a religious ecstasy, or that a real doctor would

dance about the drawing-room to show the invigorating effects of his own

medicine, as to believe that a soldier, when asked for his authority,

would point to a lot of shining weapons and declare symbolically that

might was right. Of course, a real soldier would go rather red in the

face and huskily repeat the proper formula, whatever it was, as that he

came in the King's name.

Soldiers have many faults, but they have one redeeming merit; they are

never worshippers of force. Soldiers more than any other men are taught

severely and systematically that might is not right. The fact is

obvious. The might is in the hundred men who obey. The right (or what is

held to be right) is in the one man who commands them. They learn to

obey symbols, arbitrary things, stripes on an arm, buttons on a coat, a

title, a flag. These may be artificial things; they may be unreasonable

things; they may, if you will, be wicked things; but they are weak

things. They are not Force, and they do not look like Force. They are

parts of an idea: of the idea of discipline; if you will, of the idea of

tyranny; but still an idea. No soldier could possibly say that his own

bayonets were his authority. No soldier could possibly say that he came

in the name of his own bayonets. It would be as absurd as if a postman

said that he came inside his bag. I do not, as I have said, underrate

the evils that really do arise from militarism and the military ethic.

It tends to give people wooden faces and sometimes wooden heads. It

tends moreover (both through its specialisation and through its constant

obedience) to a certain loss of real independence and strength of

character. This has almost always been found when people made the

mistake of turning the soldier into a statesman, under the mistaken

impression that he was a strong man. The Duke of Wellington, for

instance, was a strong soldier and therefore a weak statesman. But the

soldier is always, by the nature of things, loyal to something. And as

long as one is loyal to something one can never be a worshipper of mere

force. For mere force, violence in the abstract, is the enemy of

anything we love. To love anything is to see it at once under lowering

skies of danger. Loyalty implies loyalty in misfortune; and when a

soldier has accepted any nation's uniform he has already accepted its

defeat.

Nevertheless, it does appear to be possible in Germany for a man to

point to fixed bayonets and say, "These are my authority," and yet to

convince ordinarily sane men that he is a soldier. If this is so, it

does really seem to point to some habit of high-faultin' in the German

nation, such as that of which I spoke previously. It almost looks as if

the advisers, and even the officials, of the German Army had become

infected in some degree with the false and feeble doctrine that might is

right. As this doctrine is invariably preached by physical weaklings

like Nietzsche it is a very serious thing even to entertain the

supposition that it is affecting men who have really to do military work

It would be the end of German soldiers to be affected by German

philosophy. Energetic people use energy as a means, but only very tired

people ever use energy as a reason. Athletes go in for games, because

athletes desire glory. Invalids go in for calisthenics; for invalids

(alone of all human beings) desire strength. So long as the German Army

points to its heraldic eagle and says, "I come in the name of this

fierce but fabulous animal," the German Army will be all right. If ever

it says, "I come in the name of bayonets," the bayonets will break like

glass, for only the weak exhibit strength without an aim.

At the same time, as I said before, do not let us forged our own faults.

Do not let us forget them any the more easily because they are the

opposite to the German faults. Modern England is too prone to present

the spectacle of a person who is enormously delighted because he has not

got the contrary disadvantages to his own. The Englishman is always

saying "My house is not damp" at the moment when his house is on fire.

The Englishman is always saying, "I have thrown off all traces of

anaemia" in the middle of a fit of apoplexy. Let us always remember

that if an Englishman wants to swindle English people, he does not dress

up in the uniform of a soldier. If an Englishman wants to swindle

English people he would as soon think of dressing up in the uniform of a

messenger boy. Everything in England is done unofficially, casually, by

conversations and cliques. The one Parliament that really does rule

England is a secret Parliament; the debates of which must not be

published--the Cabinet. The debates of the Commons are sometimes

important; but only the debates in the Lobby, never the debates in the

House. Journalists do control public opinion; but it is not controlled

by the arguments they publish--it is controlled by the arguments between

the editor and sub-editor, which they do not publish. This casualness is

our English vice. It is at once casual and secret. Our public life is

conducted privately. Hence it follows that if an English swindler wished

to impress us, the last thing he would think of doing would be to put on

a uniform. He would put on a polite slouching air and a careless,

expensive suit of clothes; he would stroll up to the Mayor, be so

awfully sorry to disturb him, find he had forgotten his card-case,

mention, as if he were ashamed of it, that he was the Duke of Mercia,

and carry the whole thing through with the air of a man who could get

two hundred witnesses and two thousand retainers, but who was too tired

to call any of them. And if he did it very well I strongly suspect that

he would be as successful as the indefensible Captain at Koepenick.

Our tendency for many centuries past has been, not so much towards

creating an aristocracy (which may or may not be a good thing in

itself), as towards substituting an aristocracy for everything else. In

England we have an aristocracy instead of a religion. The nobility are

to the English poor what the saints and the fairies are to the Irish

poor, what the large devil with a black face was to the Scotch poor--the

poetry of life. In the same way in England we have an aristocracy

instead of a Government. We rely on a certain good humour and education

in the upper class to interpret to us our contradictory Constitution. No

educated man born of woman will be quite so absurd as the system that he

has to administer. In short, we do not get good laws to restrain bad

people. We get good people to restrain bad laws. And last of all we in

England have an aristocracy instead of an Army. We have an Army of which

the officers are proud of their families and ashamed of their uniforms.

If I were a king of any country whatever, and one of my officers were

ashamed of my uniform, I should be ashamed of my officer. Beware, then,

of the really well-bred and apologetic gentleman whose clothes are at

once quiet and fashionable, whose manner is at once diffident and frank.

Beware how you admit him into your domestic secrets, for he may be a

bogus Earl. Or, worse still, a real one.








THE BOY



I have no sympathy with international aggression when it is taken

seriously, but I have a certain dark and wild sympathy with it when it

is quite absurd. Raids are all wrong as practical politics, but they are

human and imaginable as practical jokes. In fact, almost any act of

ragging or violence can be forgiven on this strict condition--that it is

of no use at all to anybody. If the aggressor gets anything out of it,

then it is quite unpardonable. It is damned by the least hint of utility

or profit. A man of spirit and breeding may brawl, but he does not

steal. A gentleman knocks off his friend's hat; but he does not annex

his friend's hat. For this reason (as Mr. Belloc has pointed out

somewhere), the very militant French people have always returned after

their immense raids--the raids of Godfrey the Crusader, the raids of

Napoleon; "they are sucked back, having accomplished nothing but an

epic."

Sometimes I see small fragments of information in the newspapers which

make my heart leap with an irrational patriotic sympathy. I have had the

misfortune to be left comparatively cold by many of the enterprises and

proclamations of my country in recent times. But the other day I found

in the Tribune the following paragraph, which I may be permitted to

set down as an example of the kind of international outrage with which I

have by far the most instinctive sympathy. There is something

attractive, too, in the austere simplicity with which the affair is set

forth--

"Geneva, Oct. 31.

"The English schoolboy Allen, who was arrested at Lausanne railway

station on Saturday, for having painted red the statue of General Jomini

of Payerne, was liberated yesterday, after paying a fine of L24. Allen

has proceeded to Germany, where he will continue his studies. The people

of Payerne are indignant, and clamoured for his detention in prison."

Now I have no doubt that ethics and social necessity require a contrary

attitude, but I will freely confess that my first emotions on reading of

this exploit were those of profound and elemental pleasure. There is

something so large and simple about the operation of painting a whole

stone General a bright red. Of course I can understand that the people

of Payerne were indignant. They had passed to their homes at twilight

through the streets of that beautiful city (or is it a province?), and

they had seen against the silver ending of the sunset the grand grey

figure of the hero of that land remaining to guard the town under the

stars. It certainly must have been a shock to come out in the broad

white morning and find a large vermilion General staring under the

staring sun. I do not blame them at all for clamouring for the

schoolboy's detention in prison; I dare say a little detention in prison

would do him no harm. Still, I think the immense act has something about

it human and excusable; and when I endeavour to analyse the reason of

this feeling I find it to lie, not in the fact that the thing was big or

bold or successful, but in the fact that the thing was perfectly

useless to everybody, including the person who did it. The raid ends in

itself; and so Master Allen is sucked back again, having accomplished

nothing but an epic.

There is one thing which, in the presence of average modern journalism,

is perhaps worth saying in connection with such an idle matter as this.

The morals of a matter like this are exactly like the morals of anything

else; they are concerned with mutual contract, or with the rights of

independent human lives. But the whole modern world, or at any rate the

whole modern Press, has a perpetual and consuming terror of plain

morals. Men always attempt to avoid condemning a thing upon merely moral

grounds. If I beat my grandmother to death to-morrow in the middle of

Battersea Park, you may be perfectly certain that people will say

everything about it except the simple and fairly obvious fact that it is

wrong. Some will call it insane; that is, will accuse it of a deficiency

of intelligence. This is not necessarily true at all. You could not tell

whether the act was unintelligent or not unless you knew my grandmother.

Some will call it vulgar, disgusting, and the rest of it; that is, they

will accuse it of a lack of manners. Perhaps it does show a lack of

manners; but this is scarcely its most serious disadvantage. Others will

talk about the loathsome spectacle and the revolting scene; that is,

they will accuse it of a deficiency of art, or aesthetic beauty. This

again depends on the circumstances: in order to be quite certain that

the appearance of the old lady has definitely deteriorated under the

process of being beaten to death, it is necessary for the philosophical

critic to be quite certain how ugly she was before. Another school of

thinkers will say that the action is lacking in efficiency: that it is

an uneconomic waste of a good grandmother. But that could only depend on

the value, which is again an individual matter. The only real point that

is worth mentioning is that the action is wicked, because your

grandmother has a right not to be beaten to death. But of this simple

moral explanation modern journalism has, as I say, a standing fear. It

will call the action anything else--mad, bestial, vulgar, idiotic,

rather than call it sinful.

One example can be found in such cases as that of the prank of the boy

and the statue. When some trick of this sort is played, the newspapers

opposed to it always describe it as "a senseless joke." What is the good

of saying that? Every joke is a senseless joke. A joke is by its nature

a protest against sense. It is no good attacking nonsense for being

successfully nonsensical. Of course it is nonsensical to paint a

celebrated Italian General a bright red; it is as nonsensical as "Alice

in Wonderland." It is also, in my opinion, very nearly as funny. But the

real answer to the affair is not to say that it is nonsensical or even

to say that it is not funny, but to point out that it is wrong to spoil

statues which belong to other people. If the modern world will not

insist on having some sharp and definite moral law, capable of resisting

the counter-attractions of art and humour, the modern world will simply

be given over as a spoil to anybody who can manage to do a nasty thing

in a nice way. Every murderer who can murder entertainingly will be

allowed to murder. Every burglar who burgles in really humorous

attitudes will burgle as much as he likes.

There is another case of the thing that I mean. Why on earth do the

newspapers, in describing a dynamite outrage or any other political

assassination, call it a "dastardly outrage" or a cowardly outrage? It

is perfectly evident that it is not dastardly in the least. It is

perfectly evident that it is about as cowardly as the Christians going

to the lions. The man who does it exposes himself to the chance of being

torn in pieces by two thousand people. What the thing is, is not

cowardly, but profoundly and detestably wicked. The man who does it is

very infamous and very brave. But, again, the explanation is that our

modern Press would rather appeal to physical arrogance, or to anything,

rather than appeal to right and wrong.

In most of the matters of modern England, the real difficulty is that

there is a negative revolution without a positive revolution. Positive

aristocracy is breaking up without any particular appearance of positive

democracy taking its place. The polished class is becoming less polished

without becoming less of a class; the nobleman who becomes a guinea-pig

keeps all his privileges but loses some of his tradition; he becomes

less of a gentleman without becoming less of a nobleman. In the same way

(until some recent and happy revivals) it seemed highly probable that

the Church of England would cease to be a religion long before it had

ceased to be a Church. And in the same way, the vulgarisation of the

old, simple middle class does not even have the advantage of doing away

with class distinctions; the vulgar man is always the most

distinguished, for the very desire to be distinguished is vulgar.

At the same time, it must be remembered that when a class has a morality

it does not follow that it is an adequate morality. The middle-class

ethic was inadequate for some purposes; so is the public-school ethic,

the ethic of the upper classes. On this last matter of the public

schools Dr. Spenser, the Head Master of University College School, has

lately made some valuable observations. But even he, I think, overstates

the claim of the public schools. "The strong point of the English public

schools," he says, "has always lain in their efficiency as agencies for

the formation of character and for the inculcation of the great notion

of obligation which distinguishes a gentleman. On the physical and moral

sides the public-school men of England are, I believe, unequalled." And

he goes on to say that it is on the mental side that they are defective.

But, as a matter of fact, the public-school training is in the strict

sense defective upon the moral side also; it leaves out about half of

morality. Its just claim is that, like the old middle class (and the

Zulus), it trains some virtues and therefore suits some people for some

situations. Put an old English merchant to serve in an army and he would

have been irritated and clumsy. Put the men from English public schools

to rule Ireland, and they make the greatest hash in human history.

Touching the morality of the public schools, I will take one point only,

which is enough to prove the case. People have got into their heads an

extraordinary idea that English public-school boys and English youth

generally are taught to tell the truth. They are taught absolutely

nothing of the kind. At no English public school is it even suggested,

except by accident, that it is a man's duty to tell the truth. What is

suggested is something entirely different: that it is a man's duty not

to tell lies. So completely does this mistake soak through all

civilisation that we hardly ever think even of the difference between

the two things. When we say to a child, "You must tell the truth," we do

merely mean that he must refrain from verbal inaccuracies. But the thing

we never teach at all is the general duty of telling the truth, of

giving a complete and fair picture of anything we are talking about, of

not misrepresenting, not evading, not suppressing, not using plausible

arguments that we know to be unfair, not selecting unscrupulously to

prove an ex parte case, not telling all the nice stories about the

Scotch, and all the nasty stories about the Irish, not pretending to be

disinterested when you are really angry, not pretending to be angry when

you are really only avaricious. The one thing that is never taught by

any chance in the atmosphere of public schools is exactly that--that

there is a whole truth of things, and that in knowing it and speaking it

we are happy.

If any one has the smallest doubt of this neglect of truth in public

schools he can kill his doubt with one plain question. Can any one on

earth believe that if the seeing and telling of the whole truth were

really one of the ideals of the English governing class, there could

conceivably exist such a thing as the English party system? Why, the

English party system is founded upon the principle that telling the

whole truth does not matter. It is founded upon the principle that half

a truth is better than no politics. Our system deliberately turns a

crowd of men who might be impartial into irrational partisans. It

teaches some of them to tell lies and all of them to believe lies. It

gives every man an arbitrary brief that he has to work up as best he may

and defend as best he can. It turns a room full of citizens into a room

full of barristers. I know that it has many charms and virtues, fighting

and good-fellowship; it has all the charms and virtues of a game. I only

say that it would be a stark impossibility in a nation which believed in

telling the truth.






LIMERICKS AND COUNSELS OF PERFECTION



It is customary to remark that modern problems cannot easily be attacked

because they are so complex. In many cases I believe it is really

because they are so simple. Nobody would believe in such simplicity of

scoundrelism even if it were pointed out. People would say that the

truth was a charge of mere melodramatic villainy; forgetting that

nearly all villains really are melodramatic. Thus, for instance, we say

that some good measures are frustrated or some bad officials kept in

power by the press and confusion of public business; whereas very often

the reason is simple healthy human bribery. And thus especially we say

that the Yellow Press is exaggerative, over-emotional, illiterate, and

anarchical, and a hundred other long words; whereas the only objection

to it is that it tells lies. We waste our fine intellects in finding

exquisite phraseology to fit a man, when in a well-ordered society we

ought to be finding handcuffs to fit him.

This criticism of the modern type of righteous indignation must have

come into many people's minds, I think, in reading Dr. Horton's eloquent

expressions of disgust at the "corrupt Press," especially in connection

with the Limerick craze. Upon the Limerick craze itself, I fear Dr.

Horton will not have much effect; such fads perish before one has had

time to kill them. But Dr. Horton's protest may really do good if it

enables us to come to some clear understanding about what is really

wrong with the popular Press, and which means it might be useful and

which permissible to use for its reform. We do not want a censorship of

the Press; but we are long past talking about that. At present it is not

we that silence the Press; it is the Press that silences us. It is not a

case of the Commonwealth settling how much the editors shall say; it is

a case of the editors settling how much the Commonwealth shall know. If

we attack the Press we shall be rebelling, not repressing. But shall we

attack it?

Now it is just here that the chief difficulty occurs. It arises from

the very rarity and rectitude of those minds which commonly inaugurate

such crusades. I have the warmest respect for Dr. Horton's thirst after

righteousness; but it has always seemed to me that his righteousness

would be more effective without his refinement. The curse of the

Nonconformists is their universal refinement. They dimly connect being

good with being delicate, and even dapper; with not being grotesque or

loud or violent; with not sitting down on one's hat. Now it is always a

pleasure to be loud and violent, and sometimes it is a duty. Certainly

it has nothing to do with sin; a man can be loudly and violently

virtuous--nay, he can be loudly and violently saintly, though that is

not the type of saintliness that we recognise in Dr. Horton. And as for

sitting on one's hat, if it is done for any sublime object (as, for

instance, to amuse the children), it is obviously an act of very

beautiful self-sacrifice, the destruction and surrender of the symbol of

personal dignity upon the shrine of public festivity. Now it will not do

to attack the modern editor merely for being unrefined, like the great

mass of mankind. We must be able to say that he is immoral, not that he

is undignified or ridiculous. I do not mind the Yellow Press editor

sitting on his hat. My only objection to him begins to dawn when he

attempts to sit on my hat; or, indeed (as is at present the case), when

he proceeds to sit on my head.

But in reading between the lines of Dr. Horton's invective one

continually feels that he is not only angry with the popular Press for

being unscrupulous: he is partly angry with the popular Press for being

popular. He is not only irritated with Limericks for causing a mean

money-scramble; he is also partly irritated with Limericks for being

Limericks. The enormous size of the levity gets on his nerves, like the

glare and blare of Bank Holiday. Now this is a motive which, however

human and natural, must be strictly kept out of the way. It takes all

sorts to make a world; and it is not in the least necessary that

everybody should have that love of subtle and unobtrusive perfections in

the matter of manners or literature which does often go with the type of

the ethical idealist. It is not in the least desirable that everybody

should be earnest. It is highly desirable that everybody should be

honest, but that is a thing that can go quite easily with a coarse and

cheerful character. But the ineffectualness of most protests against the

abuse of the Press has been very largely due to the instinct of

democracy (and the instinct of democracy is like the instinct of one

woman, wild but quite right) that the people who were trying to purify

the Press were also trying to refine it; and to this the democracy very

naturally and very justly objected. We are justified in enforcing good

morals, for they belong to all mankind; but we are not justified in

enforcing good manners, for good manners always mean our own manners. We

have no right to purge the popular Press of all that we think vulgar or

trivial. Dr. Horton may possibly loathe and detest Limericks just as I

loathe and detest riddles; but I have no right to call them flippant

and unprofitable; there are wild people in the world who like riddles.

I am so afraid of this movement passing off into mere formless rhetoric

and platform passion that I will even come close to the earth and lay

down specifically some of the things that, in my opinion, could be, and

ought to be, done to reform the Press.

First, I would make a law, if there is none such at present, by which an

editor, proved to have published false news without reasonable

verification, should simply go to prison. This is not a question of

influences or atmospheres; the thing could be carried out as easily and

as practically as the punishment of thieves and murderers. Of course

there would be the usual statement that the guilt was that of a

subordinate. Let the accused editor have the right of proving this if he

can; if he does, let the subordinate be tried and go to prison. Two or

three good rich editors and proprietors properly locked up would take

the sting out of the Yellow Press better than centuries of Dr. Horton.

Second, it's impossible to pass over altogether the most unpleasant, but

the most important part of this problem. I will deal with it as

distantly as possible. I do not believe there is any harm whatever in

reading about murders; rather, if anything, good; for the thought of

death operates very powerfully with the poor in the creation of

brotherhood and a sense of human dignity. I do not believe there is a

pennyworth of harm in the police news, as such. Even divorce news,

though contemptible enough, can really in most cases be left to the

discretion of grown people; and how far children get hold of such

things is a problem for the home and not for the nation. But there is a

certain class of evils which a healthy man or woman can actually go

through life without knowing anything about at all. These, I say, should

be stamped and blackened out of every newspaper with the thickest black

of the Russian censor. Such cases should either be always tried in

camera or reporting them should be a punishable offence. The common

weakness of Nature and the sins that flesh is heir to we can leave

people to find in newspapers. Men can safely see in the papers what they

have already seen in the streets. They may safely find in their journals

what they have already found in themselves. But we do not want the

imaginations of rational and decent people clouded with the horrors of

some obscene insanity which has no more to do with human life than the

man in Bedlam who thinks he is a chicken. And, if this vile matter is

admitted, let it be simply with a mention of the Latin or legal name of

the crime, and with no details whatever. As it is, exactly the reverse

is true. Papers are permitted to terrify and darken the fancy of the

young with innumerable details, but not permitted to state in clean

legal language what the thing is about. They are allowed to give any

fact about the thing except the fact that it is a sin.

Third, I would do my best to introduce everywhere the practice of signed

articles. Those who urge the advantages of anonymity are either people

who do not realise the special peril of our time or they are people who

are profiting by it. It is true, but futile, for instance, to say that

there is something noble in being nameless when a whole corporate body

is bent on a consistent aim: as in an army or men building a cathedral.

The point of modern newspapers is that there is no such corporate body

and common aim; but each man can use the authority of the paper to

further his own private fads and his own private finances.


CHESTERTON-ALL THING CONSIDERED - EDWARD VII. AND SCOTLAND